Who "Believes" in the Gambler's Fallacy and Why?

Humans possess a remarkable ability to discriminate structure from randomness in the environment. However, this ability appears to be systematically biased. This is nowhere more evident than in the Gambler's Fallacy (GF)-the mistaken belief that observing an increasingly long sequence of "...

Ausführliche Beschreibung

Gespeichert in:
Bibliographische Detailangaben
Veröffentlicht in:Journal of experimental psychology. General 2017-01, Vol.146 (1), p.63-76
Hauptverfasser: Farmer, George D, Warren, Paul A, Hahn, Ulrike
Format: Artikel
Sprache:eng
Schlagworte:
Online-Zugang:Volltext
Tags: Tag hinzufügen
Keine Tags, Fügen Sie den ersten Tag hinzu!
container_end_page 76
container_issue 1
container_start_page 63
container_title Journal of experimental psychology. General
container_volume 146
creator Farmer, George D
Warren, Paul A
Hahn, Ulrike
description Humans possess a remarkable ability to discriminate structure from randomness in the environment. However, this ability appears to be systematically biased. This is nowhere more evident than in the Gambler's Fallacy (GF)-the mistaken belief that observing an increasingly long sequence of "heads" from an unbiased coin makes the occurrence of "tails" on the next trial ever more likely. Although the GF appears to provide evidence of "cognitive bias," a recent theoretical account (Hahn & Warren, 2009) has suggested the GF might be understandable if constraints on actual experience of random sources (such as attention and short term memory) are taken into account. Here we test this experiential account by exposing participants to 200 outcomes from a genuinely random (p = .5) Bernoulli process. All participants saw the same overall sequence; however, we manipulated experience across groups such that the sequence was divided into chunks of length 100, 10, or 5. Both before and after the exposure, participants (a) generated random sequences and (b) judged the randomness of presented sequences. In contrast to other accounts in the literature, the experiential account suggests that this manipulation will lead to systematic differences in postexposure behavior. Our data were strongly in line with this prediction and provide support for a general account of randomness perception in which biases are actually apt reflections of environmental statistics under experiential constraints. This suggests that deeper insight into human cognition may be gained if, instead of dismissing apparent biases as failings, we assume humans are rational under constraints.
doi_str_mv 10.1037/xge0000245
format Article
fullrecord <record><control><sourceid>proquest_pubme</sourceid><recordid>TN_cdi_pubmedcentral_primary_oai_pubmedcentral_nih_gov_5215234</recordid><sourceformat>XML</sourceformat><sourcesystem>PC</sourcesystem><sourcerecordid>1855788908</sourcerecordid><originalsourceid>FETCH-LOGICAL-a470t-b5d12dd265814cd5607d97ba598ae02942909b3671e052384ec93da233e24ace3</originalsourceid><addsrcrecordid>eNqFkctKxEAQRRtRdHxs_AAJulCUaPUr6d4oKr5AcKO4bDqd0olkkrE7Eefv7XF8b6xNLepwqMslZJ3CPgWeH7w-IsRhQs6RAdVcpyzOPBkA6CzlQsglshzC0xTiKlskS0yBFIryAYH7YZtsnmBd4QuGzaRqkm6IyYUdFTX67ZCc27q2bpLYpkzuh5OjVbLwYOuAax97hdydn92eXqbXNxdXp8fXqRU5dGkhS8rKkmVSUeFKmUFe6rywUiuLwLRgGnTBs5wiSMaVQKd5aRnnyIR1yFfI4cw77osRlg6bztvajH01sn5iWluZ35emGprH9sVIRqNQRMHOh8C3zz2Gzoyq4DCmabDtg6FKylwpDSqiW3_Qp7b3TYw3pRTkGgT9h5JcZPDu2p1RzrcheHz4epmCmdZlvuuK8MbPkF_oZz8R2JsBdmzNOEyc9V3lagyu9z4Gn8oMFZmhJuP8DZOQm5c</addsrcrecordid><sourcetype>Open Access Repository</sourcetype><iscdi>true</iscdi><recordtype>article</recordtype><pqid>1855346008</pqid></control><display><type>article</type><title>Who "Believes" in the Gambler's Fallacy and Why?</title><source>MEDLINE</source><source>EBSCOhost APA PsycARTICLES</source><creator>Farmer, George D ; Warren, Paul A ; Hahn, Ulrike</creator><contributor>Gauthier, Isabel ; Cowan, Nelson</contributor><creatorcontrib>Farmer, George D ; Warren, Paul A ; Hahn, Ulrike ; Gauthier, Isabel ; Cowan, Nelson</creatorcontrib><description>Humans possess a remarkable ability to discriminate structure from randomness in the environment. However, this ability appears to be systematically biased. This is nowhere more evident than in the Gambler's Fallacy (GF)-the mistaken belief that observing an increasingly long sequence of "heads" from an unbiased coin makes the occurrence of "tails" on the next trial ever more likely. Although the GF appears to provide evidence of "cognitive bias," a recent theoretical account (Hahn &amp; Warren, 2009) has suggested the GF might be understandable if constraints on actual experience of random sources (such as attention and short term memory) are taken into account. Here we test this experiential account by exposing participants to 200 outcomes from a genuinely random (p = .5) Bernoulli process. All participants saw the same overall sequence; however, we manipulated experience across groups such that the sequence was divided into chunks of length 100, 10, or 5. Both before and after the exposure, participants (a) generated random sequences and (b) judged the randomness of presented sequences. In contrast to other accounts in the literature, the experiential account suggests that this manipulation will lead to systematic differences in postexposure behavior. Our data were strongly in line with this prediction and provide support for a general account of randomness perception in which biases are actually apt reflections of environmental statistics under experiential constraints. This suggests that deeper insight into human cognition may be gained if, instead of dismissing apparent biases as failings, we assume humans are rational under constraints.</description><identifier>ISSN: 0096-3445</identifier><identifier>EISSN: 1939-2222</identifier><identifier>DOI: 10.1037/xge0000245</identifier><identifier>PMID: 28054813</identifier><identifier>CODEN: JPGEDD</identifier><language>eng</language><publisher>United States: American Psychological Association</publisher><subject>Adolescent ; Adult ; Attention ; Behavior ; Cognition ; Cognition &amp; reasoning ; Cognitive Bias ; Culture ; Discrimination ; Experimental psychology ; False Beliefs ; Female ; Gambling ; Gambling - psychology ; Human ; Humans ; Illusions ; Judgment ; Male ; Memory ; Memory, Short-Term ; Perceptions ; Probability Learning ; Problem Solving ; Young Adult</subject><ispartof>Journal of experimental psychology. General, 2017-01, Vol.146 (1), p.63-76</ispartof><rights>2017 The Author(s)</rights><rights>(c) 2017 APA, all rights reserved).</rights><rights>2017, The Author(s)</rights><rights>Copyright American Psychological Association Jan 2017</rights><rights>2017 The Author(s) 2017 The Author(s)</rights><lds50>peer_reviewed</lds50><oa>free_for_read</oa><woscitedreferencessubscribed>false</woscitedreferencessubscribed><citedby>FETCH-LOGICAL-a470t-b5d12dd265814cd5607d97ba598ae02942909b3671e052384ec93da233e24ace3</citedby></display><links><openurl>$$Topenurl_article</openurl><openurlfulltext>$$Topenurlfull_article</openurlfulltext><thumbnail>$$Tsyndetics_thumb_exl</thumbnail><link.rule.ids>230,314,780,784,885,27924,27925</link.rule.ids><backlink>$$Uhttps://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/28054813$$D View this record in MEDLINE/PubMed$$Hfree_for_read</backlink></links><search><contributor>Gauthier, Isabel</contributor><contributor>Cowan, Nelson</contributor><creatorcontrib>Farmer, George D</creatorcontrib><creatorcontrib>Warren, Paul A</creatorcontrib><creatorcontrib>Hahn, Ulrike</creatorcontrib><title>Who "Believes" in the Gambler's Fallacy and Why?</title><title>Journal of experimental psychology. General</title><addtitle>J Exp Psychol Gen</addtitle><description>Humans possess a remarkable ability to discriminate structure from randomness in the environment. However, this ability appears to be systematically biased. This is nowhere more evident than in the Gambler's Fallacy (GF)-the mistaken belief that observing an increasingly long sequence of "heads" from an unbiased coin makes the occurrence of "tails" on the next trial ever more likely. Although the GF appears to provide evidence of "cognitive bias," a recent theoretical account (Hahn &amp; Warren, 2009) has suggested the GF might be understandable if constraints on actual experience of random sources (such as attention and short term memory) are taken into account. Here we test this experiential account by exposing participants to 200 outcomes from a genuinely random (p = .5) Bernoulli process. All participants saw the same overall sequence; however, we manipulated experience across groups such that the sequence was divided into chunks of length 100, 10, or 5. Both before and after the exposure, participants (a) generated random sequences and (b) judged the randomness of presented sequences. In contrast to other accounts in the literature, the experiential account suggests that this manipulation will lead to systematic differences in postexposure behavior. Our data were strongly in line with this prediction and provide support for a general account of randomness perception in which biases are actually apt reflections of environmental statistics under experiential constraints. This suggests that deeper insight into human cognition may be gained if, instead of dismissing apparent biases as failings, we assume humans are rational under constraints.</description><subject>Adolescent</subject><subject>Adult</subject><subject>Attention</subject><subject>Behavior</subject><subject>Cognition</subject><subject>Cognition &amp; reasoning</subject><subject>Cognitive Bias</subject><subject>Culture</subject><subject>Discrimination</subject><subject>Experimental psychology</subject><subject>False Beliefs</subject><subject>Female</subject><subject>Gambling</subject><subject>Gambling - psychology</subject><subject>Human</subject><subject>Humans</subject><subject>Illusions</subject><subject>Judgment</subject><subject>Male</subject><subject>Memory</subject><subject>Memory, Short-Term</subject><subject>Perceptions</subject><subject>Probability Learning</subject><subject>Problem Solving</subject><subject>Young Adult</subject><issn>0096-3445</issn><issn>1939-2222</issn><fulltext>true</fulltext><rsrctype>article</rsrctype><creationdate>2017</creationdate><recordtype>article</recordtype><sourceid>EIF</sourceid><recordid>eNqFkctKxEAQRRtRdHxs_AAJulCUaPUr6d4oKr5AcKO4bDqd0olkkrE7Eefv7XF8b6xNLepwqMslZJ3CPgWeH7w-IsRhQs6RAdVcpyzOPBkA6CzlQsglshzC0xTiKlskS0yBFIryAYH7YZtsnmBd4QuGzaRqkm6IyYUdFTX67ZCc27q2bpLYpkzuh5OjVbLwYOuAax97hdydn92eXqbXNxdXp8fXqRU5dGkhS8rKkmVSUeFKmUFe6rywUiuLwLRgGnTBs5wiSMaVQKd5aRnnyIR1yFfI4cw77osRlg6bztvajH01sn5iWluZ35emGprH9sVIRqNQRMHOh8C3zz2Gzoyq4DCmabDtg6FKylwpDSqiW3_Qp7b3TYw3pRTkGgT9h5JcZPDu2p1RzrcheHz4epmCmdZlvuuK8MbPkF_oZz8R2JsBdmzNOEyc9V3lagyu9z4Gn8oMFZmhJuP8DZOQm5c</recordid><startdate>201701</startdate><enddate>201701</enddate><creator>Farmer, George D</creator><creator>Warren, Paul A</creator><creator>Hahn, Ulrike</creator><general>American Psychological Association</general><scope>CGR</scope><scope>CUY</scope><scope>CVF</scope><scope>ECM</scope><scope>EIF</scope><scope>NPM</scope><scope>AAYXX</scope><scope>CITATION</scope><scope>7RZ</scope><scope>PSYQQ</scope><scope>7X8</scope><scope>5PM</scope></search><sort><creationdate>201701</creationdate><title>Who "Believes" in the Gambler's Fallacy and Why?</title><author>Farmer, George D ; Warren, Paul A ; Hahn, Ulrike</author></sort><facets><frbrtype>5</frbrtype><frbrgroupid>cdi_FETCH-LOGICAL-a470t-b5d12dd265814cd5607d97ba598ae02942909b3671e052384ec93da233e24ace3</frbrgroupid><rsrctype>articles</rsrctype><prefilter>articles</prefilter><language>eng</language><creationdate>2017</creationdate><topic>Adolescent</topic><topic>Adult</topic><topic>Attention</topic><topic>Behavior</topic><topic>Cognition</topic><topic>Cognition &amp; reasoning</topic><topic>Cognitive Bias</topic><topic>Culture</topic><topic>Discrimination</topic><topic>Experimental psychology</topic><topic>False Beliefs</topic><topic>Female</topic><topic>Gambling</topic><topic>Gambling - psychology</topic><topic>Human</topic><topic>Humans</topic><topic>Illusions</topic><topic>Judgment</topic><topic>Male</topic><topic>Memory</topic><topic>Memory, Short-Term</topic><topic>Perceptions</topic><topic>Probability Learning</topic><topic>Problem Solving</topic><topic>Young Adult</topic><toplevel>peer_reviewed</toplevel><toplevel>online_resources</toplevel><creatorcontrib>Farmer, George D</creatorcontrib><creatorcontrib>Warren, Paul A</creatorcontrib><creatorcontrib>Hahn, Ulrike</creatorcontrib><collection>Medline</collection><collection>MEDLINE</collection><collection>MEDLINE (Ovid)</collection><collection>MEDLINE</collection><collection>MEDLINE</collection><collection>PubMed</collection><collection>CrossRef</collection><collection>Access via APA PsycArticles® (ProQuest)</collection><collection>ProQuest One Psychology</collection><collection>MEDLINE - Academic</collection><collection>PubMed Central (Full Participant titles)</collection><jtitle>Journal of experimental psychology. General</jtitle></facets><delivery><delcategory>Remote Search Resource</delcategory><fulltext>fulltext</fulltext></delivery><addata><au>Farmer, George D</au><au>Warren, Paul A</au><au>Hahn, Ulrike</au><au>Gauthier, Isabel</au><au>Cowan, Nelson</au><format>journal</format><genre>article</genre><ristype>JOUR</ristype><atitle>Who "Believes" in the Gambler's Fallacy and Why?</atitle><jtitle>Journal of experimental psychology. General</jtitle><addtitle>J Exp Psychol Gen</addtitle><date>2017-01</date><risdate>2017</risdate><volume>146</volume><issue>1</issue><spage>63</spage><epage>76</epage><pages>63-76</pages><issn>0096-3445</issn><eissn>1939-2222</eissn><coden>JPGEDD</coden><abstract>Humans possess a remarkable ability to discriminate structure from randomness in the environment. However, this ability appears to be systematically biased. This is nowhere more evident than in the Gambler's Fallacy (GF)-the mistaken belief that observing an increasingly long sequence of "heads" from an unbiased coin makes the occurrence of "tails" on the next trial ever more likely. Although the GF appears to provide evidence of "cognitive bias," a recent theoretical account (Hahn &amp; Warren, 2009) has suggested the GF might be understandable if constraints on actual experience of random sources (such as attention and short term memory) are taken into account. Here we test this experiential account by exposing participants to 200 outcomes from a genuinely random (p = .5) Bernoulli process. All participants saw the same overall sequence; however, we manipulated experience across groups such that the sequence was divided into chunks of length 100, 10, or 5. Both before and after the exposure, participants (a) generated random sequences and (b) judged the randomness of presented sequences. In contrast to other accounts in the literature, the experiential account suggests that this manipulation will lead to systematic differences in postexposure behavior. Our data were strongly in line with this prediction and provide support for a general account of randomness perception in which biases are actually apt reflections of environmental statistics under experiential constraints. This suggests that deeper insight into human cognition may be gained if, instead of dismissing apparent biases as failings, we assume humans are rational under constraints.</abstract><cop>United States</cop><pub>American Psychological Association</pub><pmid>28054813</pmid><doi>10.1037/xge0000245</doi><tpages>14</tpages><oa>free_for_read</oa></addata></record>
fulltext fulltext
identifier ISSN: 0096-3445
ispartof Journal of experimental psychology. General, 2017-01, Vol.146 (1), p.63-76
issn 0096-3445
1939-2222
language eng
recordid cdi_pubmedcentral_primary_oai_pubmedcentral_nih_gov_5215234
source MEDLINE; EBSCOhost APA PsycARTICLES
subjects Adolescent
Adult
Attention
Behavior
Cognition
Cognition & reasoning
Cognitive Bias
Culture
Discrimination
Experimental psychology
False Beliefs
Female
Gambling
Gambling - psychology
Human
Humans
Illusions
Judgment
Male
Memory
Memory, Short-Term
Perceptions
Probability Learning
Problem Solving
Young Adult
title Who "Believes" in the Gambler's Fallacy and Why?
url https://sfx.bib-bvb.de/sfx_tum?ctx_ver=Z39.88-2004&ctx_enc=info:ofi/enc:UTF-8&ctx_tim=2025-01-04T12%3A05%3A39IST&url_ver=Z39.88-2004&url_ctx_fmt=infofi/fmt:kev:mtx:ctx&rfr_id=info:sid/primo.exlibrisgroup.com:primo3-Article-proquest_pubme&rft_val_fmt=info:ofi/fmt:kev:mtx:journal&rft.genre=article&rft.atitle=Who%20%22Believes%22%20in%20the%20Gambler's%20Fallacy%20and%20Why?&rft.jtitle=Journal%20of%20experimental%20psychology.%20General&rft.au=Farmer,%20George%20D&rft.date=2017-01&rft.volume=146&rft.issue=1&rft.spage=63&rft.epage=76&rft.pages=63-76&rft.issn=0096-3445&rft.eissn=1939-2222&rft.coden=JPGEDD&rft_id=info:doi/10.1037/xge0000245&rft_dat=%3Cproquest_pubme%3E1855788908%3C/proquest_pubme%3E%3Curl%3E%3C/url%3E&disable_directlink=true&sfx.directlink=off&sfx.report_link=0&rft_id=info:oai/&rft_pqid=1855346008&rft_id=info:pmid/28054813&rfr_iscdi=true