Women’s and Provider’s Moral Reasoning About the Permissibility of Coercion in Birth: A Descriptive Ethics Study

Evidence shows that during birth women frequently experience unconsented care, coercion, and a loss of autonomy. For many countries, this contradicts both the law and medical ethics guidelines, which emphasize that competent and fully informed women’s autonomy must always be respected. To better und...

Ausführliche Beschreibung

Gespeichert in:
Bibliographische Detailangaben
Veröffentlicht in:Health care analysis 2024-09, Vol.32 (3), p.184-204
Hauptverfasser: Eichinger, Johanna, Büchler, Andrea, Arnold, Louisa, Rost, Michael
Format: Artikel
Sprache:eng
Schlagworte:
Online-Zugang:Volltext
Tags: Tag hinzufügen
Keine Tags, Fügen Sie den ersten Tag hinzu!
container_end_page 204
container_issue 3
container_start_page 184
container_title Health care analysis
container_volume 32
creator Eichinger, Johanna
Büchler, Andrea
Arnold, Louisa
Rost, Michael
description Evidence shows that during birth women frequently experience unconsented care, coercion, and a loss of autonomy. For many countries, this contradicts both the law and medical ethics guidelines, which emphasize that competent and fully informed women’s autonomy must always be respected. To better understand this discordance, we empirically describe perinatal maternity care providers’ and women’s moral deliberation surrounding coercive measures during birth. Data were obtained from 1-on-1 interviews with providers (N = 15) and women (N = 14), and a survey of women (N = 118). Analyses focused on an in-depth exploration of responses to a question on the permissibility of coercion in birth whose wording was borrowed from a Swiss medical-ethical guideline. Reasons for and against a principle permissibility of coercive measures in birth were grouped into clusters of reasons to build a coherent explanatory framework. Factors considered morally relevant when deliberating on coercion included women’s decisional capacity, beneficence/non-maleficence, authority through knowledge on the part of providers, flaws of the medical system, or the imperative to protect the most vulnerable. Also, we identified various misconceptions, such as the conviction that a pathological birth can justify coercion or that fetal rights can justifiably infringe on women’s autonomy. Information and education on the issue of coercion in birth are urgently needed to enable women to fully exercise their reproductive autonomy, to prevent long-term adverse health outcomes of women and children, and to reconcile the medical vigilance which has lead to a reduction of perinatal morbidity and mortality with women’s enfranchisement in their own care.
doi_str_mv 10.1007/s10728-024-00480-4
format Article
fullrecord <record><control><sourceid>proquest_pubme</sourceid><recordid>TN_cdi_pubmedcentral_primary_oai_pubmedcentral_nih_gov_11390788</recordid><sourceformat>XML</sourceformat><sourcesystem>PC</sourcesystem><sourcerecordid>2917863246</sourcerecordid><originalsourceid>FETCH-LOGICAL-c426t-7fd967b5cc76efaf83874e84a7c91e43064f428b714e7565a77a24b0a090420a3</originalsourceid><addsrcrecordid>eNp9kctuFDEQRVsIRELgB1ggS2zYNJTbbtvNBg1DeEhBRDzE0nJ7qmcc9dgT2z3S7PIb-T2-BCcTwmPBypbr1C3fulX1mMJzCiBfJAqyUTU0vAbgCmp-pzqkrWQ1Yx2_W-4g2ppBqw6qBymdQWlSgt2vDphqBIVOHFb5e1ij_3FxmYjxC3Iaw9YtMF4_fAzRjOQzmhS880sy68OUSV4hOcW4dim53o0u70gYyDxgtC544jx57WJevSQz8gaTjW6T3RbJcV45m8iXPC12D6t7gxkTPro5j6pvb4-_zt_XJ5_efZjPTmrLG5FrOSw6IfvWWilwMINiSnJU3EjbUeQMBB94o3pJOcpWtEZK0_AeDHTAGzDsqHq1191M_RoXFn0ujvQmurWJOx2M039XvFvpZdhqSllXdqWKwrMbhRjOJ0xZF98Wx9F4DFPSTUevVtpwUdCn_6BnYYq--NOMAgNQCtpCNXvKxpBSxOH2NxT0Vap6n6ouqerrVDUvTU_-9HHb8ivGArA9kErJLzH-nv0f2Z8R3K-M</addsrcrecordid><sourcetype>Open Access Repository</sourcetype><iscdi>true</iscdi><recordtype>article</recordtype><pqid>3103008805</pqid></control><display><type>article</type><title>Women’s and Provider’s Moral Reasoning About the Permissibility of Coercion in Birth: A Descriptive Ethics Study</title><source>Applied Social Sciences Index &amp; Abstracts (ASSIA)</source><source>MEDLINE</source><source>SpringerLink Journals - AutoHoldings</source><creator>Eichinger, Johanna ; Büchler, Andrea ; Arnold, Louisa ; Rost, Michael</creator><creatorcontrib>Eichinger, Johanna ; Büchler, Andrea ; Arnold, Louisa ; Rost, Michael</creatorcontrib><description>Evidence shows that during birth women frequently experience unconsented care, coercion, and a loss of autonomy. For many countries, this contradicts both the law and medical ethics guidelines, which emphasize that competent and fully informed women’s autonomy must always be respected. To better understand this discordance, we empirically describe perinatal maternity care providers’ and women’s moral deliberation surrounding coercive measures during birth. Data were obtained from 1-on-1 interviews with providers (N = 15) and women (N = 14), and a survey of women (N = 118). Analyses focused on an in-depth exploration of responses to a question on the permissibility of coercion in birth whose wording was borrowed from a Swiss medical-ethical guideline. Reasons for and against a principle permissibility of coercive measures in birth were grouped into clusters of reasons to build a coherent explanatory framework. Factors considered morally relevant when deliberating on coercion included women’s decisional capacity, beneficence/non-maleficence, authority through knowledge on the part of providers, flaws of the medical system, or the imperative to protect the most vulnerable. Also, we identified various misconceptions, such as the conviction that a pathological birth can justify coercion or that fetal rights can justifiably infringe on women’s autonomy. Information and education on the issue of coercion in birth are urgently needed to enable women to fully exercise their reproductive autonomy, to prevent long-term adverse health outcomes of women and children, and to reconcile the medical vigilance which has lead to a reduction of perinatal morbidity and mortality with women’s enfranchisement in their own care.</description><identifier>ISSN: 1065-3058</identifier><identifier>ISSN: 1573-3394</identifier><identifier>EISSN: 1573-3394</identifier><identifier>DOI: 10.1007/s10728-024-00480-4</identifier><identifier>PMID: 38261096</identifier><language>eng</language><publisher>New York: Springer US</publisher><subject>Adult ; Autonomy ; Bodily integrity ; Childbirth &amp; labor ; Clinical outcomes ; Coercion ; Consent ; Criminal law ; Decision making ; Decision Making - ethics ; Delivery, Obstetric - ethics ; Delivery, Obstetric - psychology ; Ethics ; Female ; Fetal rights ; Health Informatics ; Health Personnel - ethics ; Health Personnel - psychology ; Health status ; Humans ; Intervention ; Interviews as Topic ; Medical ethics ; Medical personnel ; Medicine ; Medicine &amp; Public Health ; Misconceptions ; Moral judgment ; Morals ; Morbidity ; Mothers ; Obstetrics ; Original ; Original Article ; Parturition - psychology ; Perinatal care ; Personal Autonomy ; Personhood ; Philosophy of Medicine ; Pregnancy ; Public Health ; Surveys and Questionnaires ; Switzerland ; Vigilance ; Women ; Womens health ; Wording</subject><ispartof>Health care analysis, 2024-09, Vol.32 (3), p.184-204</ispartof><rights>The Author(s) 2024</rights><rights>2024. The Author(s).</rights><rights>The Author(s) 2024. This work is published under http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ (the “License”). Notwithstanding the ProQuest Terms and Conditions, you may use this content in accordance with the terms of the License.</rights><rights>The Author(s) 2024 2024</rights><lds50>peer_reviewed</lds50><oa>free_for_read</oa><woscitedreferencessubscribed>false</woscitedreferencessubscribed><cites>FETCH-LOGICAL-c426t-7fd967b5cc76efaf83874e84a7c91e43064f428b714e7565a77a24b0a090420a3</cites><orcidid>0000-0002-0508-9070 ; 0000-0002-5301-3433 ; 0000-0001-6537-9793</orcidid></display><links><openurl>$$Topenurl_article</openurl><openurlfulltext>$$Topenurlfull_article</openurlfulltext><thumbnail>$$Tsyndetics_thumb_exl</thumbnail><linktopdf>$$Uhttps://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/s10728-024-00480-4$$EPDF$$P50$$Gspringer$$Hfree_for_read</linktopdf><linktohtml>$$Uhttps://link.springer.com/10.1007/s10728-024-00480-4$$EHTML$$P50$$Gspringer$$Hfree_for_read</linktohtml><link.rule.ids>230,314,776,780,881,27901,27902,30976,41464,42533,51294</link.rule.ids><backlink>$$Uhttps://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/38261096$$D View this record in MEDLINE/PubMed$$Hfree_for_read</backlink></links><search><creatorcontrib>Eichinger, Johanna</creatorcontrib><creatorcontrib>Büchler, Andrea</creatorcontrib><creatorcontrib>Arnold, Louisa</creatorcontrib><creatorcontrib>Rost, Michael</creatorcontrib><title>Women’s and Provider’s Moral Reasoning About the Permissibility of Coercion in Birth: A Descriptive Ethics Study</title><title>Health care analysis</title><addtitle>Health Care Anal</addtitle><addtitle>Health Care Anal</addtitle><description>Evidence shows that during birth women frequently experience unconsented care, coercion, and a loss of autonomy. For many countries, this contradicts both the law and medical ethics guidelines, which emphasize that competent and fully informed women’s autonomy must always be respected. To better understand this discordance, we empirically describe perinatal maternity care providers’ and women’s moral deliberation surrounding coercive measures during birth. Data were obtained from 1-on-1 interviews with providers (N = 15) and women (N = 14), and a survey of women (N = 118). Analyses focused on an in-depth exploration of responses to a question on the permissibility of coercion in birth whose wording was borrowed from a Swiss medical-ethical guideline. Reasons for and against a principle permissibility of coercive measures in birth were grouped into clusters of reasons to build a coherent explanatory framework. Factors considered morally relevant when deliberating on coercion included women’s decisional capacity, beneficence/non-maleficence, authority through knowledge on the part of providers, flaws of the medical system, or the imperative to protect the most vulnerable. Also, we identified various misconceptions, such as the conviction that a pathological birth can justify coercion or that fetal rights can justifiably infringe on women’s autonomy. Information and education on the issue of coercion in birth are urgently needed to enable women to fully exercise their reproductive autonomy, to prevent long-term adverse health outcomes of women and children, and to reconcile the medical vigilance which has lead to a reduction of perinatal morbidity and mortality with women’s enfranchisement in their own care.</description><subject>Adult</subject><subject>Autonomy</subject><subject>Bodily integrity</subject><subject>Childbirth &amp; labor</subject><subject>Clinical outcomes</subject><subject>Coercion</subject><subject>Consent</subject><subject>Criminal law</subject><subject>Decision making</subject><subject>Decision Making - ethics</subject><subject>Delivery, Obstetric - ethics</subject><subject>Delivery, Obstetric - psychology</subject><subject>Ethics</subject><subject>Female</subject><subject>Fetal rights</subject><subject>Health Informatics</subject><subject>Health Personnel - ethics</subject><subject>Health Personnel - psychology</subject><subject>Health status</subject><subject>Humans</subject><subject>Intervention</subject><subject>Interviews as Topic</subject><subject>Medical ethics</subject><subject>Medical personnel</subject><subject>Medicine</subject><subject>Medicine &amp; Public Health</subject><subject>Misconceptions</subject><subject>Moral judgment</subject><subject>Morals</subject><subject>Morbidity</subject><subject>Mothers</subject><subject>Obstetrics</subject><subject>Original</subject><subject>Original Article</subject><subject>Parturition - psychology</subject><subject>Perinatal care</subject><subject>Personal Autonomy</subject><subject>Personhood</subject><subject>Philosophy of Medicine</subject><subject>Pregnancy</subject><subject>Public Health</subject><subject>Surveys and Questionnaires</subject><subject>Switzerland</subject><subject>Vigilance</subject><subject>Women</subject><subject>Womens health</subject><subject>Wording</subject><issn>1065-3058</issn><issn>1573-3394</issn><issn>1573-3394</issn><fulltext>true</fulltext><rsrctype>article</rsrctype><creationdate>2024</creationdate><recordtype>article</recordtype><sourceid>C6C</sourceid><sourceid>EIF</sourceid><sourceid>7QJ</sourceid><recordid>eNp9kctuFDEQRVsIRELgB1ggS2zYNJTbbtvNBg1DeEhBRDzE0nJ7qmcc9dgT2z3S7PIb-T2-BCcTwmPBypbr1C3fulX1mMJzCiBfJAqyUTU0vAbgCmp-pzqkrWQ1Yx2_W-4g2ppBqw6qBymdQWlSgt2vDphqBIVOHFb5e1ij_3FxmYjxC3Iaw9YtMF4_fAzRjOQzmhS880sy68OUSV4hOcW4dim53o0u70gYyDxgtC544jx57WJevSQz8gaTjW6T3RbJcV45m8iXPC12D6t7gxkTPro5j6pvb4-_zt_XJ5_efZjPTmrLG5FrOSw6IfvWWilwMINiSnJU3EjbUeQMBB94o3pJOcpWtEZK0_AeDHTAGzDsqHq1191M_RoXFn0ujvQmurWJOx2M039XvFvpZdhqSllXdqWKwrMbhRjOJ0xZF98Wx9F4DFPSTUevVtpwUdCn_6BnYYq--NOMAgNQCtpCNXvKxpBSxOH2NxT0Vap6n6ouqerrVDUvTU_-9HHb8ivGArA9kErJLzH-nv0f2Z8R3K-M</recordid><startdate>20240901</startdate><enddate>20240901</enddate><creator>Eichinger, Johanna</creator><creator>Büchler, Andrea</creator><creator>Arnold, Louisa</creator><creator>Rost, Michael</creator><general>Springer US</general><general>Springer Nature B.V</general><scope>C6C</scope><scope>CGR</scope><scope>CUY</scope><scope>CVF</scope><scope>ECM</scope><scope>EIF</scope><scope>NPM</scope><scope>AAYXX</scope><scope>CITATION</scope><scope>7QJ</scope><scope>8BJ</scope><scope>FQK</scope><scope>JBE</scope><scope>K9.</scope><scope>7X8</scope><scope>5PM</scope><orcidid>https://orcid.org/0000-0002-0508-9070</orcidid><orcidid>https://orcid.org/0000-0002-5301-3433</orcidid><orcidid>https://orcid.org/0000-0001-6537-9793</orcidid></search><sort><creationdate>20240901</creationdate><title>Women’s and Provider’s Moral Reasoning About the Permissibility of Coercion in Birth: A Descriptive Ethics Study</title><author>Eichinger, Johanna ; Büchler, Andrea ; Arnold, Louisa ; Rost, Michael</author></sort><facets><frbrtype>5</frbrtype><frbrgroupid>cdi_FETCH-LOGICAL-c426t-7fd967b5cc76efaf83874e84a7c91e43064f428b714e7565a77a24b0a090420a3</frbrgroupid><rsrctype>articles</rsrctype><prefilter>articles</prefilter><language>eng</language><creationdate>2024</creationdate><topic>Adult</topic><topic>Autonomy</topic><topic>Bodily integrity</topic><topic>Childbirth &amp; labor</topic><topic>Clinical outcomes</topic><topic>Coercion</topic><topic>Consent</topic><topic>Criminal law</topic><topic>Decision making</topic><topic>Decision Making - ethics</topic><topic>Delivery, Obstetric - ethics</topic><topic>Delivery, Obstetric - psychology</topic><topic>Ethics</topic><topic>Female</topic><topic>Fetal rights</topic><topic>Health Informatics</topic><topic>Health Personnel - ethics</topic><topic>Health Personnel - psychology</topic><topic>Health status</topic><topic>Humans</topic><topic>Intervention</topic><topic>Interviews as Topic</topic><topic>Medical ethics</topic><topic>Medical personnel</topic><topic>Medicine</topic><topic>Medicine &amp; Public Health</topic><topic>Misconceptions</topic><topic>Moral judgment</topic><topic>Morals</topic><topic>Morbidity</topic><topic>Mothers</topic><topic>Obstetrics</topic><topic>Original</topic><topic>Original Article</topic><topic>Parturition - psychology</topic><topic>Perinatal care</topic><topic>Personal Autonomy</topic><topic>Personhood</topic><topic>Philosophy of Medicine</topic><topic>Pregnancy</topic><topic>Public Health</topic><topic>Surveys and Questionnaires</topic><topic>Switzerland</topic><topic>Vigilance</topic><topic>Women</topic><topic>Womens health</topic><topic>Wording</topic><toplevel>peer_reviewed</toplevel><toplevel>online_resources</toplevel><creatorcontrib>Eichinger, Johanna</creatorcontrib><creatorcontrib>Büchler, Andrea</creatorcontrib><creatorcontrib>Arnold, Louisa</creatorcontrib><creatorcontrib>Rost, Michael</creatorcontrib><collection>Springer Nature OA Free Journals</collection><collection>Medline</collection><collection>MEDLINE</collection><collection>MEDLINE (Ovid)</collection><collection>MEDLINE</collection><collection>MEDLINE</collection><collection>PubMed</collection><collection>CrossRef</collection><collection>Applied Social Sciences Index &amp; Abstracts (ASSIA)</collection><collection>International Bibliography of the Social Sciences (IBSS)</collection><collection>International Bibliography of the Social Sciences</collection><collection>International Bibliography of the Social Sciences</collection><collection>ProQuest Health &amp; Medical Complete (Alumni)</collection><collection>MEDLINE - Academic</collection><collection>PubMed Central (Full Participant titles)</collection><jtitle>Health care analysis</jtitle></facets><delivery><delcategory>Remote Search Resource</delcategory><fulltext>fulltext</fulltext></delivery><addata><au>Eichinger, Johanna</au><au>Büchler, Andrea</au><au>Arnold, Louisa</au><au>Rost, Michael</au><format>journal</format><genre>article</genre><ristype>JOUR</ristype><atitle>Women’s and Provider’s Moral Reasoning About the Permissibility of Coercion in Birth: A Descriptive Ethics Study</atitle><jtitle>Health care analysis</jtitle><stitle>Health Care Anal</stitle><addtitle>Health Care Anal</addtitle><date>2024-09-01</date><risdate>2024</risdate><volume>32</volume><issue>3</issue><spage>184</spage><epage>204</epage><pages>184-204</pages><issn>1065-3058</issn><issn>1573-3394</issn><eissn>1573-3394</eissn><abstract>Evidence shows that during birth women frequently experience unconsented care, coercion, and a loss of autonomy. For many countries, this contradicts both the law and medical ethics guidelines, which emphasize that competent and fully informed women’s autonomy must always be respected. To better understand this discordance, we empirically describe perinatal maternity care providers’ and women’s moral deliberation surrounding coercive measures during birth. Data were obtained from 1-on-1 interviews with providers (N = 15) and women (N = 14), and a survey of women (N = 118). Analyses focused on an in-depth exploration of responses to a question on the permissibility of coercion in birth whose wording was borrowed from a Swiss medical-ethical guideline. Reasons for and against a principle permissibility of coercive measures in birth were grouped into clusters of reasons to build a coherent explanatory framework. Factors considered morally relevant when deliberating on coercion included women’s decisional capacity, beneficence/non-maleficence, authority through knowledge on the part of providers, flaws of the medical system, or the imperative to protect the most vulnerable. Also, we identified various misconceptions, such as the conviction that a pathological birth can justify coercion or that fetal rights can justifiably infringe on women’s autonomy. Information and education on the issue of coercion in birth are urgently needed to enable women to fully exercise their reproductive autonomy, to prevent long-term adverse health outcomes of women and children, and to reconcile the medical vigilance which has lead to a reduction of perinatal morbidity and mortality with women’s enfranchisement in their own care.</abstract><cop>New York</cop><pub>Springer US</pub><pmid>38261096</pmid><doi>10.1007/s10728-024-00480-4</doi><tpages>21</tpages><orcidid>https://orcid.org/0000-0002-0508-9070</orcidid><orcidid>https://orcid.org/0000-0002-5301-3433</orcidid><orcidid>https://orcid.org/0000-0001-6537-9793</orcidid><oa>free_for_read</oa></addata></record>
fulltext fulltext
identifier ISSN: 1065-3058
ispartof Health care analysis, 2024-09, Vol.32 (3), p.184-204
issn 1065-3058
1573-3394
1573-3394
language eng
recordid cdi_pubmedcentral_primary_oai_pubmedcentral_nih_gov_11390788
source Applied Social Sciences Index & Abstracts (ASSIA); MEDLINE; SpringerLink Journals - AutoHoldings
subjects Adult
Autonomy
Bodily integrity
Childbirth & labor
Clinical outcomes
Coercion
Consent
Criminal law
Decision making
Decision Making - ethics
Delivery, Obstetric - ethics
Delivery, Obstetric - psychology
Ethics
Female
Fetal rights
Health Informatics
Health Personnel - ethics
Health Personnel - psychology
Health status
Humans
Intervention
Interviews as Topic
Medical ethics
Medical personnel
Medicine
Medicine & Public Health
Misconceptions
Moral judgment
Morals
Morbidity
Mothers
Obstetrics
Original
Original Article
Parturition - psychology
Perinatal care
Personal Autonomy
Personhood
Philosophy of Medicine
Pregnancy
Public Health
Surveys and Questionnaires
Switzerland
Vigilance
Women
Womens health
Wording
title Women’s and Provider’s Moral Reasoning About the Permissibility of Coercion in Birth: A Descriptive Ethics Study
url https://sfx.bib-bvb.de/sfx_tum?ctx_ver=Z39.88-2004&ctx_enc=info:ofi/enc:UTF-8&ctx_tim=2025-02-08T23%3A31%3A17IST&url_ver=Z39.88-2004&url_ctx_fmt=infofi/fmt:kev:mtx:ctx&rfr_id=info:sid/primo.exlibrisgroup.com:primo3-Article-proquest_pubme&rft_val_fmt=info:ofi/fmt:kev:mtx:journal&rft.genre=article&rft.atitle=Women%E2%80%99s%20and%20Provider%E2%80%99s%20Moral%20Reasoning%20About%20the%20Permissibility%20of%20Coercion%20in%20Birth:%20A%20Descriptive%20Ethics%20Study&rft.jtitle=Health%20care%20analysis&rft.au=Eichinger,%20Johanna&rft.date=2024-09-01&rft.volume=32&rft.issue=3&rft.spage=184&rft.epage=204&rft.pages=184-204&rft.issn=1065-3058&rft.eissn=1573-3394&rft_id=info:doi/10.1007/s10728-024-00480-4&rft_dat=%3Cproquest_pubme%3E2917863246%3C/proquest_pubme%3E%3Curl%3E%3C/url%3E&disable_directlink=true&sfx.directlink=off&sfx.report_link=0&rft_id=info:oai/&rft_pqid=3103008805&rft_id=info:pmid/38261096&rfr_iscdi=true