Would a Reasonable Person Now Accept the 1968 Harvard Brain Death Report? A Short History of Brain Death
When The Ad Hoc Committee of Harvard Medical School to Examine the Definition of Brain Death began meeting in 1967, I was a graduate student, with committee member Ralph Potter and committee chair Henry Beecher as my mentors. The question of when to stop life support on a severely compromised patien...
Gespeichert in:
Veröffentlicht in: | The Hastings Center report 2018-11, Vol.48 (S4), p.S6-S9 |
---|---|
1. Verfasser: | |
Format: | Artikel |
Sprache: | eng |
Schlagworte: | |
Online-Zugang: | Volltext |
Tags: |
Tag hinzufügen
Keine Tags, Fügen Sie den ersten Tag hinzu!
|
container_end_page | S9 |
---|---|
container_issue | S4 |
container_start_page | S6 |
container_title | The Hastings Center report |
container_volume | 48 |
creator | Veatch, Robert M. |
description | When The Ad Hoc Committee of Harvard Medical School to Examine the Definition of Brain Death began meeting in 1967, I was a graduate student, with committee member Ralph Potter and committee chair Henry Beecher as my mentors. The question of when to stop life support on a severely compromised patient was not clearly differentiated from the question of when someone was dead. A serious clinical problem arose when physicians realized that a patient's condition was hopeless but life support perpetuated body function. Thus, the committee stated that its first purpose was to deal with the burdens on patients and families as well as on hospitals and on patients needing hospital beds occupied by comatose patients. They intuited the strategy of “defining” these patients as dead, thus legitimating treatment stoppage. They noted that this would also serve a second purpose. Although the dead donor rule had not yet been clearly articulated, they claimed that defining patients as dead would also address controversy over obtaining organs for transplant.
My mentors’ discussions related to my interest in the intersection between questions primarily of medical fact (When has a human brain irreversibly ceased functioning?) and nonmedical questions of social policy (Should we treat individuals with dead brains and beating hearts as dead humans?). It quickly became clear that most committee members did not appreciate the interplay of these questions. |
doi_str_mv | 10.1002/hast.943 |
format | Article |
fullrecord | <record><control><sourceid>proquest_cross</sourceid><recordid>TN_cdi_proquest_miscellaneous_2160728740</recordid><sourceformat>XML</sourceformat><sourcesystem>PC</sourcesystem><sourcerecordid>2160728740</sourcerecordid><originalsourceid>FETCH-LOGICAL-c2983-423155373342b0c61c3895ce0784923d0c1ca798ec39856f718759863be338af3</originalsourceid><addsrcrecordid>eNp1kEtLw0AQxxdRbK2Cn0AWvHhJ3Uceuyep9RGhqNiK3sJmsyEpaTbuJpZ-e7e2PhCcy8zhNz9m_gAcYzTECJHzQth2yH26A_o4CIiH_fB1F_QR4tRDlPo9cGDtHLnyGd0HPYoC5rMg6oPiRXdVBgV8UsLqWqSVgo_KuBHe6yUcSamaFraFgpiHDMbCvAuTwUsjyhpeKdEWbrPRpr2AIzgt3ADj0rbarKDOf2OHYC8XlVVH2z4AzzfXs3HsTR5u78ajiScJZ9TzCXUf0MgdTVIkQywp44FUKGI-JzRDEksRcaYk5SwI8wizKOAspKmilImcDsDZxtsY_dYp2yaL0kpVVaJWurMJwSGKCIt85NDTP-hcd6Z2131SmDmK_wil0dYalSeNKRfCrBKMknX6yTr9xKXv0JOtsEsXKvsGv-J2gLcBlmWlVv-Kkng0na2FH_uiilY</addsrcrecordid><sourcetype>Aggregation Database</sourcetype><iscdi>true</iscdi><recordtype>article</recordtype><pqid>2160188749</pqid></control><display><type>article</type><title>Would a Reasonable Person Now Accept the 1968 Harvard Brain Death Report? A Short History of Brain Death</title><source>Wiley Online Library Journals Frontfile Complete</source><source>Jstor Complete Legacy</source><creator>Veatch, Robert M.</creator><creatorcontrib>Veatch, Robert M.</creatorcontrib><description>When The Ad Hoc Committee of Harvard Medical School to Examine the Definition of Brain Death began meeting in 1967, I was a graduate student, with committee member Ralph Potter and committee chair Henry Beecher as my mentors. The question of when to stop life support on a severely compromised patient was not clearly differentiated from the question of when someone was dead. A serious clinical problem arose when physicians realized that a patient's condition was hopeless but life support perpetuated body function. Thus, the committee stated that its first purpose was to deal with the burdens on patients and families as well as on hospitals and on patients needing hospital beds occupied by comatose patients. They intuited the strategy of “defining” these patients as dead, thus legitimating treatment stoppage. They noted that this would also serve a second purpose. Although the dead donor rule had not yet been clearly articulated, they claimed that defining patients as dead would also address controversy over obtaining organs for transplant.
My mentors’ discussions related to my interest in the intersection between questions primarily of medical fact (When has a human brain irreversibly ceased functioning?) and nonmedical questions of social policy (Should we treat individuals with dead brains and beating hearts as dead humans?). It quickly became clear that most committee members did not appreciate the interplay of these questions.</description><identifier>ISSN: 0093-0334</identifier><identifier>EISSN: 1552-146X</identifier><identifier>DOI: 10.1002/hast.943</identifier><identifier>PMID: 30584857</identifier><language>eng</language><publisher>United States: Blackwell Publishing Ltd</publisher><subject>Brain death ; History of medicine ; Informed consent ; Medical ethics ; Patients rights</subject><ispartof>The Hastings Center report, 2018-11, Vol.48 (S4), p.S6-S9</ispartof><rights>2018 The Hastings Center</rights><rights>2018 The Hastings Center.</rights><lds50>peer_reviewed</lds50><oa>free_for_read</oa><woscitedreferencessubscribed>false</woscitedreferencessubscribed><citedby>FETCH-LOGICAL-c2983-423155373342b0c61c3895ce0784923d0c1ca798ec39856f718759863be338af3</citedby><cites>FETCH-LOGICAL-c2983-423155373342b0c61c3895ce0784923d0c1ca798ec39856f718759863be338af3</cites></display><links><openurl>$$Topenurl_article</openurl><openurlfulltext>$$Topenurlfull_article</openurlfulltext><thumbnail>$$Tsyndetics_thumb_exl</thumbnail><linktopdf>$$Uhttps://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/pdf/10.1002%2Fhast.943$$EPDF$$P50$$Gwiley$$H</linktopdf><linktohtml>$$Uhttps://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/full/10.1002%2Fhast.943$$EHTML$$P50$$Gwiley$$H</linktohtml><link.rule.ids>314,777,781,1412,27905,27906,45555,45556</link.rule.ids><backlink>$$Uhttps://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/30584857$$D View this record in MEDLINE/PubMed$$Hfree_for_read</backlink></links><search><creatorcontrib>Veatch, Robert M.</creatorcontrib><title>Would a Reasonable Person Now Accept the 1968 Harvard Brain Death Report? A Short History of Brain Death</title><title>The Hastings Center report</title><addtitle>Hastings Cent Rep</addtitle><description>When The Ad Hoc Committee of Harvard Medical School to Examine the Definition of Brain Death began meeting in 1967, I was a graduate student, with committee member Ralph Potter and committee chair Henry Beecher as my mentors. The question of when to stop life support on a severely compromised patient was not clearly differentiated from the question of when someone was dead. A serious clinical problem arose when physicians realized that a patient's condition was hopeless but life support perpetuated body function. Thus, the committee stated that its first purpose was to deal with the burdens on patients and families as well as on hospitals and on patients needing hospital beds occupied by comatose patients. They intuited the strategy of “defining” these patients as dead, thus legitimating treatment stoppage. They noted that this would also serve a second purpose. Although the dead donor rule had not yet been clearly articulated, they claimed that defining patients as dead would also address controversy over obtaining organs for transplant.
My mentors’ discussions related to my interest in the intersection between questions primarily of medical fact (When has a human brain irreversibly ceased functioning?) and nonmedical questions of social policy (Should we treat individuals with dead brains and beating hearts as dead humans?). It quickly became clear that most committee members did not appreciate the interplay of these questions.</description><subject>Brain death</subject><subject>History of medicine</subject><subject>Informed consent</subject><subject>Medical ethics</subject><subject>Patients rights</subject><issn>0093-0334</issn><issn>1552-146X</issn><fulltext>true</fulltext><rsrctype>article</rsrctype><creationdate>2018</creationdate><recordtype>article</recordtype><recordid>eNp1kEtLw0AQxxdRbK2Cn0AWvHhJ3Uceuyep9RGhqNiK3sJmsyEpaTbuJpZ-e7e2PhCcy8zhNz9m_gAcYzTECJHzQth2yH26A_o4CIiH_fB1F_QR4tRDlPo9cGDtHLnyGd0HPYoC5rMg6oPiRXdVBgV8UsLqWqSVgo_KuBHe6yUcSamaFraFgpiHDMbCvAuTwUsjyhpeKdEWbrPRpr2AIzgt3ADj0rbarKDOf2OHYC8XlVVH2z4AzzfXs3HsTR5u78ajiScJZ9TzCXUf0MgdTVIkQywp44FUKGI-JzRDEksRcaYk5SwI8wizKOAspKmilImcDsDZxtsY_dYp2yaL0kpVVaJWurMJwSGKCIt85NDTP-hcd6Z2131SmDmK_wil0dYalSeNKRfCrBKMknX6yTr9xKXv0JOtsEsXKvsGv-J2gLcBlmWlVv-Kkng0na2FH_uiilY</recordid><startdate>201811</startdate><enddate>201811</enddate><creator>Veatch, Robert M.</creator><general>Blackwell Publishing Ltd</general><scope>NPM</scope><scope>AAYXX</scope><scope>CITATION</scope><scope>K9.</scope><scope>NAPCQ</scope><scope>7X8</scope></search><sort><creationdate>201811</creationdate><title>Would a Reasonable Person Now Accept the 1968 Harvard Brain Death Report? A Short History of Brain Death</title><author>Veatch, Robert M.</author></sort><facets><frbrtype>5</frbrtype><frbrgroupid>cdi_FETCH-LOGICAL-c2983-423155373342b0c61c3895ce0784923d0c1ca798ec39856f718759863be338af3</frbrgroupid><rsrctype>articles</rsrctype><prefilter>articles</prefilter><language>eng</language><creationdate>2018</creationdate><topic>Brain death</topic><topic>History of medicine</topic><topic>Informed consent</topic><topic>Medical ethics</topic><topic>Patients rights</topic><toplevel>peer_reviewed</toplevel><toplevel>online_resources</toplevel><creatorcontrib>Veatch, Robert M.</creatorcontrib><collection>PubMed</collection><collection>CrossRef</collection><collection>ProQuest Health & Medical Complete (Alumni)</collection><collection>Nursing & Allied Health Premium</collection><collection>MEDLINE - Academic</collection><jtitle>The Hastings Center report</jtitle></facets><delivery><delcategory>Remote Search Resource</delcategory><fulltext>fulltext</fulltext></delivery><addata><au>Veatch, Robert M.</au><format>journal</format><genre>article</genre><ristype>JOUR</ristype><atitle>Would a Reasonable Person Now Accept the 1968 Harvard Brain Death Report? A Short History of Brain Death</atitle><jtitle>The Hastings Center report</jtitle><addtitle>Hastings Cent Rep</addtitle><date>2018-11</date><risdate>2018</risdate><volume>48</volume><issue>S4</issue><spage>S6</spage><epage>S9</epage><pages>S6-S9</pages><issn>0093-0334</issn><eissn>1552-146X</eissn><abstract>When The Ad Hoc Committee of Harvard Medical School to Examine the Definition of Brain Death began meeting in 1967, I was a graduate student, with committee member Ralph Potter and committee chair Henry Beecher as my mentors. The question of when to stop life support on a severely compromised patient was not clearly differentiated from the question of when someone was dead. A serious clinical problem arose when physicians realized that a patient's condition was hopeless but life support perpetuated body function. Thus, the committee stated that its first purpose was to deal with the burdens on patients and families as well as on hospitals and on patients needing hospital beds occupied by comatose patients. They intuited the strategy of “defining” these patients as dead, thus legitimating treatment stoppage. They noted that this would also serve a second purpose. Although the dead donor rule had not yet been clearly articulated, they claimed that defining patients as dead would also address controversy over obtaining organs for transplant.
My mentors’ discussions related to my interest in the intersection between questions primarily of medical fact (When has a human brain irreversibly ceased functioning?) and nonmedical questions of social policy (Should we treat individuals with dead brains and beating hearts as dead humans?). It quickly became clear that most committee members did not appreciate the interplay of these questions.</abstract><cop>United States</cop><pub>Blackwell Publishing Ltd</pub><pmid>30584857</pmid><doi>10.1002/hast.943</doi><tpages>4</tpages><oa>free_for_read</oa></addata></record> |
fulltext | fulltext |
identifier | ISSN: 0093-0334 |
ispartof | The Hastings Center report, 2018-11, Vol.48 (S4), p.S6-S9 |
issn | 0093-0334 1552-146X |
language | eng |
recordid | cdi_proquest_miscellaneous_2160728740 |
source | Wiley Online Library Journals Frontfile Complete; Jstor Complete Legacy |
subjects | Brain death History of medicine Informed consent Medical ethics Patients rights |
title | Would a Reasonable Person Now Accept the 1968 Harvard Brain Death Report? A Short History of Brain Death |
url | https://sfx.bib-bvb.de/sfx_tum?ctx_ver=Z39.88-2004&ctx_enc=info:ofi/enc:UTF-8&ctx_tim=2025-01-17T22%3A46%3A43IST&url_ver=Z39.88-2004&url_ctx_fmt=infofi/fmt:kev:mtx:ctx&rfr_id=info:sid/primo.exlibrisgroup.com:primo3-Article-proquest_cross&rft_val_fmt=info:ofi/fmt:kev:mtx:journal&rft.genre=article&rft.atitle=Would%20a%20Reasonable%20Person%20Now%20Accept%20the%201968%20Harvard%20Brain%20Death%20Report?%20A%20Short%20History%20of%20Brain%20Death&rft.jtitle=The%20Hastings%20Center%20report&rft.au=Veatch,%20Robert%20M.&rft.date=2018-11&rft.volume=48&rft.issue=S4&rft.spage=S6&rft.epage=S9&rft.pages=S6-S9&rft.issn=0093-0334&rft.eissn=1552-146X&rft_id=info:doi/10.1002/hast.943&rft_dat=%3Cproquest_cross%3E2160728740%3C/proquest_cross%3E%3Curl%3E%3C/url%3E&disable_directlink=true&sfx.directlink=off&sfx.report_link=0&rft_id=info:oai/&rft_pqid=2160188749&rft_id=info:pmid/30584857&rfr_iscdi=true |