On substituted arguments

Clinicians who follow their approach, 'reinterpreting' the substituted judgement standard, could be risking potential legal liability unless the standard is changed. [...]if the intention of Wendler and Phillips is to respect patient autonomy, it is curious that they make no use of data de...

Ausführliche Beschreibung

Gespeichert in:
Bibliographische Detailangaben
Veröffentlicht in:Journal of medical ethics 2015-09, Vol.41 (9), p.732-733
Hauptverfasser: Sulmasy, Daniel P, Sulmasy, Lois Snyder
Format: Artikel
Sprache:eng
Schlagworte:
Online-Zugang:Volltext
Tags: Tag hinzufügen
Keine Tags, Fügen Sie den ersten Tag hinzu!
container_end_page 733
container_issue 9
container_start_page 732
container_title Journal of medical ethics
container_volume 41
creator Sulmasy, Daniel P
Sulmasy, Lois Snyder
description Clinicians who follow their approach, 'reinterpreting' the substituted judgement standard, could be risking potential legal liability unless the standard is changed. [...]if the intention of Wendler and Phillips is to respect patient autonomy, it is curious that they make no use of data demonstrating that the majority of patients do not want decisions to be guided solely according to their own treatment preferences anyway, but would like to see equal or exclusive weight given to the judgements of their loved ones in making medical decisions for them should they become incapable of deciding for themselves. 5 Thus the question, 'What would your loved one want were she able to speak to us today?' is not the best approximation of the authentic values of most patients and seems disrespectful of their meta-autonomous choices about how they make decisions and how they should be treated. [...]in the example Wendler and Phillips give of a Jehovah's Witness, the Substituted Interests Model would arrive at the same decision as their model: the authentic values and real interests of this patient, as a unique person, would highlight the patient's allegiance to the will of Jehovah and would therefore lead to a decision against transfusion.
doi_str_mv 10.1136/medethics-2014-102503
format Article
fullrecord <record><control><sourceid>jstor_proqu</sourceid><recordid>TN_cdi_proquest_miscellaneous_1707557532</recordid><sourceformat>XML</sourceformat><sourcesystem>PC</sourcesystem><jstor_id>44014199</jstor_id><sourcerecordid>44014199</sourcerecordid><originalsourceid>FETCH-LOGICAL-b433t-8d79b275456709b10ccacd1fb853597933c2010f88f6fd823ae1280756166d93</originalsourceid><addsrcrecordid>eNqNkD1PwzAQhi0EoqWwsxRVYmEJnL_tEVXlQ6rUpbuVOA4kapJiOwP_HlcpHZi4xcM99975QWiO4RFjKp5aV7r4WduQEcAsw0A40DM0xUzSjBEuz9EUKIhMKIAJugqhgVRE6Us0IVxIKoWaottNtwhDEWIdh-jKRe4_htZ1MVyjiyrfBXdzfGdo-7LaLt-y9eb1ffm8zgpGacxUKXVBJGcpEXSBwdrclrgqFKdcS02pTfdBpVQlqlIRmjtMFEgusBClpjP0MMbuff81uBBNWwfrdru8c_0QDJaJ5ZJTktD7P2jTD75LxyVKYdCKg0wUHynr-xC8q8ze123uvw0GczBnTubMwZwZzaW5u2P6UCTiNPWrKgHzEWhC7P2pz1gKwfrwExj7Rdv8c-cP2RqBmw</addsrcrecordid><sourcetype>Aggregation Database</sourcetype><iscdi>true</iscdi><recordtype>article</recordtype><pqid>1781098507</pqid></control><display><type>article</type><title>On substituted arguments</title><source>MEDLINE</source><source>BMJ Journals - NESLi2</source><source>JSTOR Archive Collection A-Z Listing</source><creator>Sulmasy, Daniel P ; Sulmasy, Lois Snyder</creator><creatorcontrib>Sulmasy, Daniel P ; Sulmasy, Lois Snyder</creatorcontrib><description>Clinicians who follow their approach, 'reinterpreting' the substituted judgement standard, could be risking potential legal liability unless the standard is changed. [...]if the intention of Wendler and Phillips is to respect patient autonomy, it is curious that they make no use of data demonstrating that the majority of patients do not want decisions to be guided solely according to their own treatment preferences anyway, but would like to see equal or exclusive weight given to the judgements of their loved ones in making medical decisions for them should they become incapable of deciding for themselves. 5 Thus the question, 'What would your loved one want were she able to speak to us today?' is not the best approximation of the authentic values of most patients and seems disrespectful of their meta-autonomous choices about how they make decisions and how they should be treated. [...]in the example Wendler and Phillips give of a Jehovah's Witness, the Substituted Interests Model would arrive at the same decision as their model: the authentic values and real interests of this patient, as a unique person, would highlight the patient's allegiance to the will of Jehovah and would therefore lead to a decision against transfusion.</description><identifier>ISSN: 0306-6800</identifier><identifier>EISSN: 1473-4257</identifier><identifier>DOI: 10.1136/medethics-2014-102503</identifier><identifier>PMID: 25673768</identifier><identifier>CODEN: JMETDR</identifier><language>eng</language><publisher>England: Institute of Medical Ethics and BMJ Publishing Group Ltd</publisher><subject>Bioethics ; Commentary ; Decision making ; Decision Making - ethics ; Humans ; Judgment ; Mental Competency ; Patients ; Personal Autonomy ; Proxy ; Value of Life ; Values</subject><ispartof>Journal of medical ethics, 2015-09, Vol.41 (9), p.732-733</ispartof><rights>Published by the BMJ Publishing Group Limited. For permission to use (where not already granted under a licence) please go to http://group.bmj.com/group/rights-licensing/permissions</rights><rights>2015 BMJ Publishing Group Ltd and the Institute of Medical Ethics</rights><rights>Copyright: 2015 Published by the BMJ Publishing Group Limited. For permission to use (where not already granted under a licence) please go to http://group.bmj.com/group/rights-licensing/permissions</rights><lds50>peer_reviewed</lds50><woscitedreferencessubscribed>false</woscitedreferencessubscribed><citedby>FETCH-LOGICAL-b433t-8d79b275456709b10ccacd1fb853597933c2010f88f6fd823ae1280756166d93</citedby><cites>FETCH-LOGICAL-b433t-8d79b275456709b10ccacd1fb853597933c2010f88f6fd823ae1280756166d93</cites></display><links><openurl>$$Topenurl_article</openurl><openurlfulltext>$$Topenurlfull_article</openurlfulltext><thumbnail>$$Tsyndetics_thumb_exl</thumbnail><linktopdf>$$Uhttps://jme.bmj.com/content/41/9/732.full.pdf$$EPDF$$P50$$Gbmj$$H</linktopdf><linktohtml>$$Uhttps://jme.bmj.com/content/41/9/732.full$$EHTML$$P50$$Gbmj$$H</linktohtml><link.rule.ids>114,115,314,780,784,803,3196,23571,27924,27925,58017,58250,77600,77631</link.rule.ids><backlink>$$Uhttps://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/25673768$$D View this record in MEDLINE/PubMed$$Hfree_for_read</backlink></links><search><creatorcontrib>Sulmasy, Daniel P</creatorcontrib><creatorcontrib>Sulmasy, Lois Snyder</creatorcontrib><title>On substituted arguments</title><title>Journal of medical ethics</title><addtitle>J Med Ethics</addtitle><description>Clinicians who follow their approach, 'reinterpreting' the substituted judgement standard, could be risking potential legal liability unless the standard is changed. [...]if the intention of Wendler and Phillips is to respect patient autonomy, it is curious that they make no use of data demonstrating that the majority of patients do not want decisions to be guided solely according to their own treatment preferences anyway, but would like to see equal or exclusive weight given to the judgements of their loved ones in making medical decisions for them should they become incapable of deciding for themselves. 5 Thus the question, 'What would your loved one want were she able to speak to us today?' is not the best approximation of the authentic values of most patients and seems disrespectful of their meta-autonomous choices about how they make decisions and how they should be treated. [...]in the example Wendler and Phillips give of a Jehovah's Witness, the Substituted Interests Model would arrive at the same decision as their model: the authentic values and real interests of this patient, as a unique person, would highlight the patient's allegiance to the will of Jehovah and would therefore lead to a decision against transfusion.</description><subject>Bioethics</subject><subject>Commentary</subject><subject>Decision making</subject><subject>Decision Making - ethics</subject><subject>Humans</subject><subject>Judgment</subject><subject>Mental Competency</subject><subject>Patients</subject><subject>Personal Autonomy</subject><subject>Proxy</subject><subject>Value of Life</subject><subject>Values</subject><issn>0306-6800</issn><issn>1473-4257</issn><fulltext>true</fulltext><rsrctype>article</rsrctype><creationdate>2015</creationdate><recordtype>article</recordtype><sourceid>EIF</sourceid><sourceid>8G5</sourceid><sourceid>ABUWG</sourceid><sourceid>AFKRA</sourceid><sourceid>AVQMV</sourceid><sourceid>AZQEC</sourceid><sourceid>BENPR</sourceid><sourceid>CCPQU</sourceid><sourceid>DWQXO</sourceid><sourceid>GNUQQ</sourceid><sourceid>GUQSH</sourceid><sourceid>K50</sourceid><sourceid>M1D</sourceid><sourceid>M2O</sourceid><recordid>eNqNkD1PwzAQhi0EoqWwsxRVYmEJnL_tEVXlQ6rUpbuVOA4kapJiOwP_HlcpHZi4xcM99975QWiO4RFjKp5aV7r4WduQEcAsw0A40DM0xUzSjBEuz9EUKIhMKIAJugqhgVRE6Us0IVxIKoWaottNtwhDEWIdh-jKRe4_htZ1MVyjiyrfBXdzfGdo-7LaLt-y9eb1ffm8zgpGacxUKXVBJGcpEXSBwdrclrgqFKdcS02pTfdBpVQlqlIRmjtMFEgusBClpjP0MMbuff81uBBNWwfrdru8c_0QDJaJ5ZJTktD7P2jTD75LxyVKYdCKg0wUHynr-xC8q8ze123uvw0GczBnTubMwZwZzaW5u2P6UCTiNPWrKgHzEWhC7P2pz1gKwfrwExj7Rdv8c-cP2RqBmw</recordid><startdate>20150901</startdate><enddate>20150901</enddate><creator>Sulmasy, Daniel P</creator><creator>Sulmasy, Lois Snyder</creator><general>Institute of Medical Ethics and BMJ Publishing Group Ltd</general><general>BMJ Publishing Group LTD</general><scope>CGR</scope><scope>CUY</scope><scope>CVF</scope><scope>ECM</scope><scope>EIF</scope><scope>NPM</scope><scope>AAYXX</scope><scope>CITATION</scope><scope>0-V</scope><scope>3V.</scope><scope>7RV</scope><scope>7X7</scope><scope>7XB</scope><scope>88E</scope><scope>88I</scope><scope>88J</scope><scope>8AF</scope><scope>8FI</scope><scope>8FJ</scope><scope>8FK</scope><scope>8G5</scope><scope>AABKS</scope><scope>ABSDQ</scope><scope>ABUWG</scope><scope>AFKRA</scope><scope>ALSLI</scope><scope>AVQMV</scope><scope>AZQEC</scope><scope>BENPR</scope><scope>BTHHO</scope><scope>CCPQU</scope><scope>DWQXO</scope><scope>FYUFA</scope><scope>GHDGH</scope><scope>GNUQQ</scope><scope>GUQSH</scope><scope>HCIFZ</scope><scope>K50</scope><scope>K9.</scope><scope>KB0</scope><scope>M0S</scope><scope>M1D</scope><scope>M1P</scope><scope>M2O</scope><scope>M2P</scope><scope>M2R</scope><scope>MBDVC</scope><scope>NAPCQ</scope><scope>PQEST</scope><scope>PQQKQ</scope><scope>PQUKI</scope><scope>PRINS</scope><scope>Q9U</scope><scope>7X8</scope></search><sort><creationdate>20150901</creationdate><title>On substituted arguments</title><author>Sulmasy, Daniel P ; Sulmasy, Lois Snyder</author></sort><facets><frbrtype>5</frbrtype><frbrgroupid>cdi_FETCH-LOGICAL-b433t-8d79b275456709b10ccacd1fb853597933c2010f88f6fd823ae1280756166d93</frbrgroupid><rsrctype>articles</rsrctype><prefilter>articles</prefilter><language>eng</language><creationdate>2015</creationdate><topic>Bioethics</topic><topic>Commentary</topic><topic>Decision making</topic><topic>Decision Making - ethics</topic><topic>Humans</topic><topic>Judgment</topic><topic>Mental Competency</topic><topic>Patients</topic><topic>Personal Autonomy</topic><topic>Proxy</topic><topic>Value of Life</topic><topic>Values</topic><toplevel>peer_reviewed</toplevel><toplevel>online_resources</toplevel><creatorcontrib>Sulmasy, Daniel P</creatorcontrib><creatorcontrib>Sulmasy, Lois Snyder</creatorcontrib><collection>Medline</collection><collection>MEDLINE</collection><collection>MEDLINE (Ovid)</collection><collection>MEDLINE</collection><collection>MEDLINE</collection><collection>PubMed</collection><collection>CrossRef</collection><collection>ProQuest Social Sciences Premium Collection</collection><collection>ProQuest Central (Corporate)</collection><collection>Nursing &amp; Allied Health Database</collection><collection>Health &amp; Medical Collection</collection><collection>ProQuest Central (purchase pre-March 2016)</collection><collection>Medical Database (Alumni Edition)</collection><collection>Science Database (Alumni Edition)</collection><collection>Social Science Database (Alumni Edition)</collection><collection>STEM Database</collection><collection>Hospital Premium Collection</collection><collection>Hospital Premium Collection (Alumni Edition)</collection><collection>ProQuest Central (Alumni) (purchase pre-March 2016)</collection><collection>Research Library (Alumni Edition)</collection><collection>Philosophy Collection</collection><collection>Philosophy Database</collection><collection>ProQuest Central (Alumni Edition)</collection><collection>ProQuest Central UK/Ireland</collection><collection>Social Science Premium Collection</collection><collection>Arts Premium Collection</collection><collection>ProQuest Central Essentials</collection><collection>ProQuest Central</collection><collection>BMJ Journals</collection><collection>ProQuest One Community College</collection><collection>ProQuest Central Korea</collection><collection>Health Research Premium Collection</collection><collection>Health Research Premium Collection (Alumni)</collection><collection>ProQuest Central Student</collection><collection>Research Library Prep</collection><collection>SciTech Premium Collection</collection><collection>Art, Design &amp; Architecture Collection</collection><collection>ProQuest Health &amp; Medical Complete (Alumni)</collection><collection>Nursing &amp; Allied Health Database (Alumni Edition)</collection><collection>Health &amp; Medical Collection (Alumni Edition)</collection><collection>Arts &amp; Humanities Database</collection><collection>Medical Database</collection><collection>Research Library</collection><collection>Science Database</collection><collection>Social Science Database</collection><collection>Research Library (Corporate)</collection><collection>Nursing &amp; Allied Health Premium</collection><collection>ProQuest One Academic Eastern Edition (DO NOT USE)</collection><collection>ProQuest One Academic</collection><collection>ProQuest One Academic UKI Edition</collection><collection>ProQuest Central China</collection><collection>ProQuest Central Basic</collection><collection>MEDLINE - Academic</collection><jtitle>Journal of medical ethics</jtitle></facets><delivery><delcategory>Remote Search Resource</delcategory><fulltext>fulltext</fulltext></delivery><addata><au>Sulmasy, Daniel P</au><au>Sulmasy, Lois Snyder</au><format>journal</format><genre>article</genre><ristype>JOUR</ristype><atitle>On substituted arguments</atitle><jtitle>Journal of medical ethics</jtitle><addtitle>J Med Ethics</addtitle><date>2015-09-01</date><risdate>2015</risdate><volume>41</volume><issue>9</issue><spage>732</spage><epage>733</epage><pages>732-733</pages><issn>0306-6800</issn><eissn>1473-4257</eissn><coden>JMETDR</coden><abstract>Clinicians who follow their approach, 'reinterpreting' the substituted judgement standard, could be risking potential legal liability unless the standard is changed. [...]if the intention of Wendler and Phillips is to respect patient autonomy, it is curious that they make no use of data demonstrating that the majority of patients do not want decisions to be guided solely according to their own treatment preferences anyway, but would like to see equal or exclusive weight given to the judgements of their loved ones in making medical decisions for them should they become incapable of deciding for themselves. 5 Thus the question, 'What would your loved one want were she able to speak to us today?' is not the best approximation of the authentic values of most patients and seems disrespectful of their meta-autonomous choices about how they make decisions and how they should be treated. [...]in the example Wendler and Phillips give of a Jehovah's Witness, the Substituted Interests Model would arrive at the same decision as their model: the authentic values and real interests of this patient, as a unique person, would highlight the patient's allegiance to the will of Jehovah and would therefore lead to a decision against transfusion.</abstract><cop>England</cop><pub>Institute of Medical Ethics and BMJ Publishing Group Ltd</pub><pmid>25673768</pmid><doi>10.1136/medethics-2014-102503</doi><tpages>2</tpages></addata></record>
fulltext fulltext
identifier ISSN: 0306-6800
ispartof Journal of medical ethics, 2015-09, Vol.41 (9), p.732-733
issn 0306-6800
1473-4257
language eng
recordid cdi_proquest_miscellaneous_1707557532
source MEDLINE; BMJ Journals - NESLi2; JSTOR Archive Collection A-Z Listing
subjects Bioethics
Commentary
Decision making
Decision Making - ethics
Humans
Judgment
Mental Competency
Patients
Personal Autonomy
Proxy
Value of Life
Values
title On substituted arguments
url https://sfx.bib-bvb.de/sfx_tum?ctx_ver=Z39.88-2004&ctx_enc=info:ofi/enc:UTF-8&ctx_tim=2025-01-05T06%3A14%3A49IST&url_ver=Z39.88-2004&url_ctx_fmt=infofi/fmt:kev:mtx:ctx&rfr_id=info:sid/primo.exlibrisgroup.com:primo3-Article-jstor_proqu&rft_val_fmt=info:ofi/fmt:kev:mtx:journal&rft.genre=article&rft.atitle=On%20substituted%20arguments&rft.jtitle=Journal%20of%20medical%20ethics&rft.au=Sulmasy,%20Daniel%20P&rft.date=2015-09-01&rft.volume=41&rft.issue=9&rft.spage=732&rft.epage=733&rft.pages=732-733&rft.issn=0306-6800&rft.eissn=1473-4257&rft.coden=JMETDR&rft_id=info:doi/10.1136/medethics-2014-102503&rft_dat=%3Cjstor_proqu%3E44014199%3C/jstor_proqu%3E%3Curl%3E%3C/url%3E&disable_directlink=true&sfx.directlink=off&sfx.report_link=0&rft_id=info:oai/&rft_pqid=1781098507&rft_id=info:pmid/25673768&rft_jstor_id=44014199&rfr_iscdi=true