On substituted arguments
Clinicians who follow their approach, 'reinterpreting' the substituted judgement standard, could be risking potential legal liability unless the standard is changed. [...]if the intention of Wendler and Phillips is to respect patient autonomy, it is curious that they make no use of data de...
Gespeichert in:
Veröffentlicht in: | Journal of medical ethics 2015-09, Vol.41 (9), p.732-733 |
---|---|
Hauptverfasser: | , |
Format: | Artikel |
Sprache: | eng |
Schlagworte: | |
Online-Zugang: | Volltext |
Tags: |
Tag hinzufügen
Keine Tags, Fügen Sie den ersten Tag hinzu!
|
container_end_page | 733 |
---|---|
container_issue | 9 |
container_start_page | 732 |
container_title | Journal of medical ethics |
container_volume | 41 |
creator | Sulmasy, Daniel P Sulmasy, Lois Snyder |
description | Clinicians who follow their approach, 'reinterpreting' the substituted judgement standard, could be risking potential legal liability unless the standard is changed. [...]if the intention of Wendler and Phillips is to respect patient autonomy, it is curious that they make no use of data demonstrating that the majority of patients do not want decisions to be guided solely according to their own treatment preferences anyway, but would like to see equal or exclusive weight given to the judgements of their loved ones in making medical decisions for them should they become incapable of deciding for themselves. 5 Thus the question, 'What would your loved one want were she able to speak to us today?' is not the best approximation of the authentic values of most patients and seems disrespectful of their meta-autonomous choices about how they make decisions and how they should be treated. [...]in the example Wendler and Phillips give of a Jehovah's Witness, the Substituted Interests Model would arrive at the same decision as their model: the authentic values and real interests of this patient, as a unique person, would highlight the patient's allegiance to the will of Jehovah and would therefore lead to a decision against transfusion. |
doi_str_mv | 10.1136/medethics-2014-102503 |
format | Article |
fullrecord | <record><control><sourceid>jstor_proqu</sourceid><recordid>TN_cdi_proquest_miscellaneous_1707557532</recordid><sourceformat>XML</sourceformat><sourcesystem>PC</sourcesystem><jstor_id>44014199</jstor_id><sourcerecordid>44014199</sourcerecordid><originalsourceid>FETCH-LOGICAL-b433t-8d79b275456709b10ccacd1fb853597933c2010f88f6fd823ae1280756166d93</originalsourceid><addsrcrecordid>eNqNkD1PwzAQhi0EoqWwsxRVYmEJnL_tEVXlQ6rUpbuVOA4kapJiOwP_HlcpHZi4xcM99975QWiO4RFjKp5aV7r4WduQEcAsw0A40DM0xUzSjBEuz9EUKIhMKIAJugqhgVRE6Us0IVxIKoWaottNtwhDEWIdh-jKRe4_htZ1MVyjiyrfBXdzfGdo-7LaLt-y9eb1ffm8zgpGacxUKXVBJGcpEXSBwdrclrgqFKdcS02pTfdBpVQlqlIRmjtMFEgusBClpjP0MMbuff81uBBNWwfrdru8c_0QDJaJ5ZJTktD7P2jTD75LxyVKYdCKg0wUHynr-xC8q8ze123uvw0GczBnTubMwZwZzaW5u2P6UCTiNPWrKgHzEWhC7P2pz1gKwfrwExj7Rdv8c-cP2RqBmw</addsrcrecordid><sourcetype>Aggregation Database</sourcetype><iscdi>true</iscdi><recordtype>article</recordtype><pqid>1781098507</pqid></control><display><type>article</type><title>On substituted arguments</title><source>MEDLINE</source><source>BMJ Journals - NESLi2</source><source>JSTOR Archive Collection A-Z Listing</source><creator>Sulmasy, Daniel P ; Sulmasy, Lois Snyder</creator><creatorcontrib>Sulmasy, Daniel P ; Sulmasy, Lois Snyder</creatorcontrib><description>Clinicians who follow their approach, 'reinterpreting' the substituted judgement standard, could be risking potential legal liability unless the standard is changed. [...]if the intention of Wendler and Phillips is to respect patient autonomy, it is curious that they make no use of data demonstrating that the majority of patients do not want decisions to be guided solely according to their own treatment preferences anyway, but would like to see equal or exclusive weight given to the judgements of their loved ones in making medical decisions for them should they become incapable of deciding for themselves. 5 Thus the question, 'What would your loved one want were she able to speak to us today?' is not the best approximation of the authentic values of most patients and seems disrespectful of their meta-autonomous choices about how they make decisions and how they should be treated. [...]in the example Wendler and Phillips give of a Jehovah's Witness, the Substituted Interests Model would arrive at the same decision as their model: the authentic values and real interests of this patient, as a unique person, would highlight the patient's allegiance to the will of Jehovah and would therefore lead to a decision against transfusion.</description><identifier>ISSN: 0306-6800</identifier><identifier>EISSN: 1473-4257</identifier><identifier>DOI: 10.1136/medethics-2014-102503</identifier><identifier>PMID: 25673768</identifier><identifier>CODEN: JMETDR</identifier><language>eng</language><publisher>England: Institute of Medical Ethics and BMJ Publishing Group Ltd</publisher><subject>Bioethics ; Commentary ; Decision making ; Decision Making - ethics ; Humans ; Judgment ; Mental Competency ; Patients ; Personal Autonomy ; Proxy ; Value of Life ; Values</subject><ispartof>Journal of medical ethics, 2015-09, Vol.41 (9), p.732-733</ispartof><rights>Published by the BMJ Publishing Group Limited. For permission to use (where not already granted under a licence) please go to http://group.bmj.com/group/rights-licensing/permissions</rights><rights>2015 BMJ Publishing Group Ltd and the Institute of Medical Ethics</rights><rights>Copyright: 2015 Published by the BMJ Publishing Group Limited. For permission to use (where not already granted under a licence) please go to http://group.bmj.com/group/rights-licensing/permissions</rights><lds50>peer_reviewed</lds50><woscitedreferencessubscribed>false</woscitedreferencessubscribed><citedby>FETCH-LOGICAL-b433t-8d79b275456709b10ccacd1fb853597933c2010f88f6fd823ae1280756166d93</citedby><cites>FETCH-LOGICAL-b433t-8d79b275456709b10ccacd1fb853597933c2010f88f6fd823ae1280756166d93</cites></display><links><openurl>$$Topenurl_article</openurl><openurlfulltext>$$Topenurlfull_article</openurlfulltext><thumbnail>$$Tsyndetics_thumb_exl</thumbnail><linktopdf>$$Uhttps://jme.bmj.com/content/41/9/732.full.pdf$$EPDF$$P50$$Gbmj$$H</linktopdf><linktohtml>$$Uhttps://jme.bmj.com/content/41/9/732.full$$EHTML$$P50$$Gbmj$$H</linktohtml><link.rule.ids>114,115,314,780,784,803,3196,23571,27924,27925,58017,58250,77600,77631</link.rule.ids><backlink>$$Uhttps://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/25673768$$D View this record in MEDLINE/PubMed$$Hfree_for_read</backlink></links><search><creatorcontrib>Sulmasy, Daniel P</creatorcontrib><creatorcontrib>Sulmasy, Lois Snyder</creatorcontrib><title>On substituted arguments</title><title>Journal of medical ethics</title><addtitle>J Med Ethics</addtitle><description>Clinicians who follow their approach, 'reinterpreting' the substituted judgement standard, could be risking potential legal liability unless the standard is changed. [...]if the intention of Wendler and Phillips is to respect patient autonomy, it is curious that they make no use of data demonstrating that the majority of patients do not want decisions to be guided solely according to their own treatment preferences anyway, but would like to see equal or exclusive weight given to the judgements of their loved ones in making medical decisions for them should they become incapable of deciding for themselves. 5 Thus the question, 'What would your loved one want were she able to speak to us today?' is not the best approximation of the authentic values of most patients and seems disrespectful of their meta-autonomous choices about how they make decisions and how they should be treated. [...]in the example Wendler and Phillips give of a Jehovah's Witness, the Substituted Interests Model would arrive at the same decision as their model: the authentic values and real interests of this patient, as a unique person, would highlight the patient's allegiance to the will of Jehovah and would therefore lead to a decision against transfusion.</description><subject>Bioethics</subject><subject>Commentary</subject><subject>Decision making</subject><subject>Decision Making - ethics</subject><subject>Humans</subject><subject>Judgment</subject><subject>Mental Competency</subject><subject>Patients</subject><subject>Personal Autonomy</subject><subject>Proxy</subject><subject>Value of Life</subject><subject>Values</subject><issn>0306-6800</issn><issn>1473-4257</issn><fulltext>true</fulltext><rsrctype>article</rsrctype><creationdate>2015</creationdate><recordtype>article</recordtype><sourceid>EIF</sourceid><sourceid>8G5</sourceid><sourceid>ABUWG</sourceid><sourceid>AFKRA</sourceid><sourceid>AVQMV</sourceid><sourceid>AZQEC</sourceid><sourceid>BENPR</sourceid><sourceid>CCPQU</sourceid><sourceid>DWQXO</sourceid><sourceid>GNUQQ</sourceid><sourceid>GUQSH</sourceid><sourceid>K50</sourceid><sourceid>M1D</sourceid><sourceid>M2O</sourceid><recordid>eNqNkD1PwzAQhi0EoqWwsxRVYmEJnL_tEVXlQ6rUpbuVOA4kapJiOwP_HlcpHZi4xcM99975QWiO4RFjKp5aV7r4WduQEcAsw0A40DM0xUzSjBEuz9EUKIhMKIAJugqhgVRE6Us0IVxIKoWaottNtwhDEWIdh-jKRe4_htZ1MVyjiyrfBXdzfGdo-7LaLt-y9eb1ffm8zgpGacxUKXVBJGcpEXSBwdrclrgqFKdcS02pTfdBpVQlqlIRmjtMFEgusBClpjP0MMbuff81uBBNWwfrdru8c_0QDJaJ5ZJTktD7P2jTD75LxyVKYdCKg0wUHynr-xC8q8ze123uvw0GczBnTubMwZwZzaW5u2P6UCTiNPWrKgHzEWhC7P2pz1gKwfrwExj7Rdv8c-cP2RqBmw</recordid><startdate>20150901</startdate><enddate>20150901</enddate><creator>Sulmasy, Daniel P</creator><creator>Sulmasy, Lois Snyder</creator><general>Institute of Medical Ethics and BMJ Publishing Group Ltd</general><general>BMJ Publishing Group LTD</general><scope>CGR</scope><scope>CUY</scope><scope>CVF</scope><scope>ECM</scope><scope>EIF</scope><scope>NPM</scope><scope>AAYXX</scope><scope>CITATION</scope><scope>0-V</scope><scope>3V.</scope><scope>7RV</scope><scope>7X7</scope><scope>7XB</scope><scope>88E</scope><scope>88I</scope><scope>88J</scope><scope>8AF</scope><scope>8FI</scope><scope>8FJ</scope><scope>8FK</scope><scope>8G5</scope><scope>AABKS</scope><scope>ABSDQ</scope><scope>ABUWG</scope><scope>AFKRA</scope><scope>ALSLI</scope><scope>AVQMV</scope><scope>AZQEC</scope><scope>BENPR</scope><scope>BTHHO</scope><scope>CCPQU</scope><scope>DWQXO</scope><scope>FYUFA</scope><scope>GHDGH</scope><scope>GNUQQ</scope><scope>GUQSH</scope><scope>HCIFZ</scope><scope>K50</scope><scope>K9.</scope><scope>KB0</scope><scope>M0S</scope><scope>M1D</scope><scope>M1P</scope><scope>M2O</scope><scope>M2P</scope><scope>M2R</scope><scope>MBDVC</scope><scope>NAPCQ</scope><scope>PQEST</scope><scope>PQQKQ</scope><scope>PQUKI</scope><scope>PRINS</scope><scope>Q9U</scope><scope>7X8</scope></search><sort><creationdate>20150901</creationdate><title>On substituted arguments</title><author>Sulmasy, Daniel P ; Sulmasy, Lois Snyder</author></sort><facets><frbrtype>5</frbrtype><frbrgroupid>cdi_FETCH-LOGICAL-b433t-8d79b275456709b10ccacd1fb853597933c2010f88f6fd823ae1280756166d93</frbrgroupid><rsrctype>articles</rsrctype><prefilter>articles</prefilter><language>eng</language><creationdate>2015</creationdate><topic>Bioethics</topic><topic>Commentary</topic><topic>Decision making</topic><topic>Decision Making - ethics</topic><topic>Humans</topic><topic>Judgment</topic><topic>Mental Competency</topic><topic>Patients</topic><topic>Personal Autonomy</topic><topic>Proxy</topic><topic>Value of Life</topic><topic>Values</topic><toplevel>peer_reviewed</toplevel><toplevel>online_resources</toplevel><creatorcontrib>Sulmasy, Daniel P</creatorcontrib><creatorcontrib>Sulmasy, Lois Snyder</creatorcontrib><collection>Medline</collection><collection>MEDLINE</collection><collection>MEDLINE (Ovid)</collection><collection>MEDLINE</collection><collection>MEDLINE</collection><collection>PubMed</collection><collection>CrossRef</collection><collection>ProQuest Social Sciences Premium Collection</collection><collection>ProQuest Central (Corporate)</collection><collection>Nursing & Allied Health Database</collection><collection>Health & Medical Collection</collection><collection>ProQuest Central (purchase pre-March 2016)</collection><collection>Medical Database (Alumni Edition)</collection><collection>Science Database (Alumni Edition)</collection><collection>Social Science Database (Alumni Edition)</collection><collection>STEM Database</collection><collection>Hospital Premium Collection</collection><collection>Hospital Premium Collection (Alumni Edition)</collection><collection>ProQuest Central (Alumni) (purchase pre-March 2016)</collection><collection>Research Library (Alumni Edition)</collection><collection>Philosophy Collection</collection><collection>Philosophy Database</collection><collection>ProQuest Central (Alumni Edition)</collection><collection>ProQuest Central UK/Ireland</collection><collection>Social Science Premium Collection</collection><collection>Arts Premium Collection</collection><collection>ProQuest Central Essentials</collection><collection>ProQuest Central</collection><collection>BMJ Journals</collection><collection>ProQuest One Community College</collection><collection>ProQuest Central Korea</collection><collection>Health Research Premium Collection</collection><collection>Health Research Premium Collection (Alumni)</collection><collection>ProQuest Central Student</collection><collection>Research Library Prep</collection><collection>SciTech Premium Collection</collection><collection>Art, Design & Architecture Collection</collection><collection>ProQuest Health & Medical Complete (Alumni)</collection><collection>Nursing & Allied Health Database (Alumni Edition)</collection><collection>Health & Medical Collection (Alumni Edition)</collection><collection>Arts & Humanities Database</collection><collection>Medical Database</collection><collection>Research Library</collection><collection>Science Database</collection><collection>Social Science Database</collection><collection>Research Library (Corporate)</collection><collection>Nursing & Allied Health Premium</collection><collection>ProQuest One Academic Eastern Edition (DO NOT USE)</collection><collection>ProQuest One Academic</collection><collection>ProQuest One Academic UKI Edition</collection><collection>ProQuest Central China</collection><collection>ProQuest Central Basic</collection><collection>MEDLINE - Academic</collection><jtitle>Journal of medical ethics</jtitle></facets><delivery><delcategory>Remote Search Resource</delcategory><fulltext>fulltext</fulltext></delivery><addata><au>Sulmasy, Daniel P</au><au>Sulmasy, Lois Snyder</au><format>journal</format><genre>article</genre><ristype>JOUR</ristype><atitle>On substituted arguments</atitle><jtitle>Journal of medical ethics</jtitle><addtitle>J Med Ethics</addtitle><date>2015-09-01</date><risdate>2015</risdate><volume>41</volume><issue>9</issue><spage>732</spage><epage>733</epage><pages>732-733</pages><issn>0306-6800</issn><eissn>1473-4257</eissn><coden>JMETDR</coden><abstract>Clinicians who follow their approach, 'reinterpreting' the substituted judgement standard, could be risking potential legal liability unless the standard is changed. [...]if the intention of Wendler and Phillips is to respect patient autonomy, it is curious that they make no use of data demonstrating that the majority of patients do not want decisions to be guided solely according to their own treatment preferences anyway, but would like to see equal or exclusive weight given to the judgements of their loved ones in making medical decisions for them should they become incapable of deciding for themselves. 5 Thus the question, 'What would your loved one want were she able to speak to us today?' is not the best approximation of the authentic values of most patients and seems disrespectful of their meta-autonomous choices about how they make decisions and how they should be treated. [...]in the example Wendler and Phillips give of a Jehovah's Witness, the Substituted Interests Model would arrive at the same decision as their model: the authentic values and real interests of this patient, as a unique person, would highlight the patient's allegiance to the will of Jehovah and would therefore lead to a decision against transfusion.</abstract><cop>England</cop><pub>Institute of Medical Ethics and BMJ Publishing Group Ltd</pub><pmid>25673768</pmid><doi>10.1136/medethics-2014-102503</doi><tpages>2</tpages></addata></record> |
fulltext | fulltext |
identifier | ISSN: 0306-6800 |
ispartof | Journal of medical ethics, 2015-09, Vol.41 (9), p.732-733 |
issn | 0306-6800 1473-4257 |
language | eng |
recordid | cdi_proquest_miscellaneous_1707557532 |
source | MEDLINE; BMJ Journals - NESLi2; JSTOR Archive Collection A-Z Listing |
subjects | Bioethics Commentary Decision making Decision Making - ethics Humans Judgment Mental Competency Patients Personal Autonomy Proxy Value of Life Values |
title | On substituted arguments |
url | https://sfx.bib-bvb.de/sfx_tum?ctx_ver=Z39.88-2004&ctx_enc=info:ofi/enc:UTF-8&ctx_tim=2025-01-05T06%3A14%3A49IST&url_ver=Z39.88-2004&url_ctx_fmt=infofi/fmt:kev:mtx:ctx&rfr_id=info:sid/primo.exlibrisgroup.com:primo3-Article-jstor_proqu&rft_val_fmt=info:ofi/fmt:kev:mtx:journal&rft.genre=article&rft.atitle=On%20substituted%20arguments&rft.jtitle=Journal%20of%20medical%20ethics&rft.au=Sulmasy,%20Daniel%20P&rft.date=2015-09-01&rft.volume=41&rft.issue=9&rft.spage=732&rft.epage=733&rft.pages=732-733&rft.issn=0306-6800&rft.eissn=1473-4257&rft.coden=JMETDR&rft_id=info:doi/10.1136/medethics-2014-102503&rft_dat=%3Cjstor_proqu%3E44014199%3C/jstor_proqu%3E%3Curl%3E%3C/url%3E&disable_directlink=true&sfx.directlink=off&sfx.report_link=0&rft_id=info:oai/&rft_pqid=1781098507&rft_id=info:pmid/25673768&rft_jstor_id=44014199&rfr_iscdi=true |