How to Study Adaptation (and Why To Do It That Way)
Some adaptationist explanations are regarded as maximally solid and others fanciful just-so stories. Just-so stories are explanations based on very little evidence. Lack of evidence leads to circular-sounding reasoning: “this trait was shaped by selection in unseen ancestral populations and this sel...
Gespeichert in:
Veröffentlicht in: | The Quarterly review of biology 2015-06, Vol.90 (2), p.167-191 |
---|---|
Hauptverfasser: | , |
Format: | Artikel |
Sprache: | eng |
Schlagworte: | |
Online-Zugang: | Volltext |
Tags: |
Tag hinzufügen
Keine Tags, Fügen Sie den ersten Tag hinzu!
|
container_end_page | 191 |
---|---|
container_issue | 2 |
container_start_page | 167 |
container_title | The Quarterly review of biology |
container_volume | 90 |
creator | Olson, Mark E. Arroyo-Santos, Alfonso |
description | Some adaptationist explanations are regarded as maximally solid and others fanciful just-so stories. Just-so stories are explanations based on very little evidence. Lack of evidence leads to circular-sounding reasoning: “this trait was shaped by selection in unseen ancestral populations and this selection must have occurred because the trait is present.” Well-supported adaptationist explanations include evidence that is not only abundant but selected from comparative, populational, and optimality perspectives, the three adaptationist subdisciplines. Each subdiscipline obtains its broad relevance in evolutionary biology via assumptions that can only be tested with the methods of the other subdisciplines. However, even in the best-supported explanations, assumptions regarding variation, heritability, and fitness in unseen ancestral populations are always present. These assumptions are accepted given how well they would explain the data if they were true. This means that some degree of “circularity” is present in all evolutionary explanations. Evolutionary explanation corresponds not to a deductive structure, as biologists usually assert, but instead to ones such as abduction or Bayesianism. With these structures in mind, we show the way to a healthier view of “circularity” in evolutionary biology and why integration across the comparative, populational, and optimality approaches is necessary. |
doi_str_mv | 10.1086/681438 |
format | Article |
fullrecord | <record><control><sourceid>jstor_proqu</sourceid><recordid>TN_cdi_proquest_miscellaneous_1705734807</recordid><sourceformat>XML</sourceformat><sourcesystem>PC</sourcesystem><jstor_id>10.1086/681438</jstor_id><sourcerecordid>10.1086/681438</sourcerecordid><originalsourceid>FETCH-LOGICAL-c462t-40e614b591851d124ffd8d51bbabb19535da50c3cadbc2a536db5c525fb21ec13</originalsourceid><addsrcrecordid>eNqNkM1KAzEYRYMotlZ9BAkoUhejySSZJMtS_woFF1a6HPI3tqVtxkkG6ds7pbUFQXT1bQ7nfvcCcI7RLUYiu8sEpkQcgDZmRCacY3EI2ggRkjDOUQuchDBDCEkm0TFopVkqGGG0Dciz_4TRw9dY2xXsWVVGFad-CbtqaeF4soIjD-89HEQ4mqgIx2p1cwqOCjUP7mx7O-Dt8WHUf06GL0-Dfm-YGJqlMaHIZZhqJrFg2OKUFoUVlmGtldZYNvlWMWSIUVabVDGSWc0MS1mhU-wMJh3Q3XjLyn_ULsR8MQ3Gzedq6XwdcswR44QKxP9GM0klZ1SurZc_0Jmvq2VTpKEEkZJSvhZebyhT-RAqV-RlNV2oapVjlK8XzzeLN-DFVlfrhbM77HviBrjaALWZTI1692XlQtiH7jzdf2B5aYt9g1mIvvrtsS9hXJxy</addsrcrecordid><sourcetype>Aggregation Database</sourcetype><iscdi>true</iscdi><recordtype>article</recordtype><pqid>1683994477</pqid></control><display><type>article</type><title>How to Study Adaptation (and Why To Do It That Way)</title><source>Jstor Complete Legacy</source><source>MEDLINE</source><creator>Olson, Mark E. ; Arroyo-Santos, Alfonso</creator><contributor>Handling Editor Daniel E. Dykhuizen</contributor><creatorcontrib>Olson, Mark E. ; Arroyo-Santos, Alfonso ; Handling Editor Daniel E. Dykhuizen</creatorcontrib><description>Some adaptationist explanations are regarded as maximally solid and others fanciful just-so stories. Just-so stories are explanations based on very little evidence. Lack of evidence leads to circular-sounding reasoning: “this trait was shaped by selection in unseen ancestral populations and this selection must have occurred because the trait is present.” Well-supported adaptationist explanations include evidence that is not only abundant but selected from comparative, populational, and optimality perspectives, the three adaptationist subdisciplines. Each subdiscipline obtains its broad relevance in evolutionary biology via assumptions that can only be tested with the methods of the other subdisciplines. However, even in the best-supported explanations, assumptions regarding variation, heritability, and fitness in unseen ancestral populations are always present. These assumptions are accepted given how well they would explain the data if they were true. This means that some degree of “circularity” is present in all evolutionary explanations. Evolutionary explanation corresponds not to a deductive structure, as biologists usually assert, but instead to ones such as abduction or Bayesianism. With these structures in mind, we show the way to a healthier view of “circularity” in evolutionary biology and why integration across the comparative, populational, and optimality approaches is necessary.</description><identifier>ISSN: 0033-5770</identifier><identifier>EISSN: 1539-7718</identifier><identifier>DOI: 10.1086/681438</identifier><identifier>PMID: 26285354</identifier><identifier>CODEN: QRBIAK</identifier><language>eng</language><publisher>United States: The University of Chicago Press</publisher><subject>Adaptability ; Adaptation, Physiological ; Animals ; Bayes Theorem ; Biological adaptation ; Biological Evolution ; Biologists ; Biology ; Direct evidence ; Ecological competition ; Evolutionary biology ; Heritability ; Hypothetico deductive model ; Phenotypic traits ; Population characteristics ; Reasoning</subject><ispartof>The Quarterly review of biology, 2015-06, Vol.90 (2), p.167-191</ispartof><rights>Copyright © 2015 by The University of Chicago Press. All rights reserved.</rights><rights>Copyright University of Chicago, acting through its Press Jun 2015</rights><lds50>peer_reviewed</lds50><oa>free_for_read</oa><woscitedreferencessubscribed>false</woscitedreferencessubscribed><citedby>FETCH-LOGICAL-c462t-40e614b591851d124ffd8d51bbabb19535da50c3cadbc2a536db5c525fb21ec13</citedby><cites>FETCH-LOGICAL-c462t-40e614b591851d124ffd8d51bbabb19535da50c3cadbc2a536db5c525fb21ec13</cites></display><links><openurl>$$Topenurl_article</openurl><openurlfulltext>$$Topenurlfull_article</openurlfulltext><thumbnail>$$Tsyndetics_thumb_exl</thumbnail><link.rule.ids>314,780,784,803,27924,27925</link.rule.ids><backlink>$$Uhttps://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/26285354$$D View this record in MEDLINE/PubMed$$Hfree_for_read</backlink></links><search><contributor>Handling Editor Daniel E. Dykhuizen</contributor><creatorcontrib>Olson, Mark E.</creatorcontrib><creatorcontrib>Arroyo-Santos, Alfonso</creatorcontrib><title>How to Study Adaptation (and Why To Do It That Way)</title><title>The Quarterly review of biology</title><addtitle>Q Rev Biol</addtitle><description>Some adaptationist explanations are regarded as maximally solid and others fanciful just-so stories. Just-so stories are explanations based on very little evidence. Lack of evidence leads to circular-sounding reasoning: “this trait was shaped by selection in unseen ancestral populations and this selection must have occurred because the trait is present.” Well-supported adaptationist explanations include evidence that is not only abundant but selected from comparative, populational, and optimality perspectives, the three adaptationist subdisciplines. Each subdiscipline obtains its broad relevance in evolutionary biology via assumptions that can only be tested with the methods of the other subdisciplines. However, even in the best-supported explanations, assumptions regarding variation, heritability, and fitness in unseen ancestral populations are always present. These assumptions are accepted given how well they would explain the data if they were true. This means that some degree of “circularity” is present in all evolutionary explanations. Evolutionary explanation corresponds not to a deductive structure, as biologists usually assert, but instead to ones such as abduction or Bayesianism. With these structures in mind, we show the way to a healthier view of “circularity” in evolutionary biology and why integration across the comparative, populational, and optimality approaches is necessary.</description><subject>Adaptability</subject><subject>Adaptation, Physiological</subject><subject>Animals</subject><subject>Bayes Theorem</subject><subject>Biological adaptation</subject><subject>Biological Evolution</subject><subject>Biologists</subject><subject>Biology</subject><subject>Direct evidence</subject><subject>Ecological competition</subject><subject>Evolutionary biology</subject><subject>Heritability</subject><subject>Hypothetico deductive model</subject><subject>Phenotypic traits</subject><subject>Population characteristics</subject><subject>Reasoning</subject><issn>0033-5770</issn><issn>1539-7718</issn><fulltext>true</fulltext><rsrctype>article</rsrctype><creationdate>2015</creationdate><recordtype>article</recordtype><sourceid>EIF</sourceid><recordid>eNqNkM1KAzEYRYMotlZ9BAkoUhejySSZJMtS_woFF1a6HPI3tqVtxkkG6ds7pbUFQXT1bQ7nfvcCcI7RLUYiu8sEpkQcgDZmRCacY3EI2ggRkjDOUQuchDBDCEkm0TFopVkqGGG0Dciz_4TRw9dY2xXsWVVGFad-CbtqaeF4soIjD-89HEQ4mqgIx2p1cwqOCjUP7mx7O-Dt8WHUf06GL0-Dfm-YGJqlMaHIZZhqJrFg2OKUFoUVlmGtldZYNvlWMWSIUVabVDGSWc0MS1mhU-wMJh3Q3XjLyn_ULsR8MQ3Gzedq6XwdcswR44QKxP9GM0klZ1SurZc_0Jmvq2VTpKEEkZJSvhZebyhT-RAqV-RlNV2oapVjlK8XzzeLN-DFVlfrhbM77HviBrjaALWZTI1692XlQtiH7jzdf2B5aYt9g1mIvvrtsS9hXJxy</recordid><startdate>20150601</startdate><enddate>20150601</enddate><creator>Olson, Mark E.</creator><creator>Arroyo-Santos, Alfonso</creator><general>The University of Chicago Press</general><general>University of Chicago, acting through its Press</general><scope>CGR</scope><scope>CUY</scope><scope>CVF</scope><scope>ECM</scope><scope>EIF</scope><scope>NPM</scope><scope>AAYXX</scope><scope>CITATION</scope><scope>7QG</scope><scope>7QL</scope><scope>7QP</scope><scope>7QR</scope><scope>7SN</scope><scope>7SS</scope><scope>7T7</scope><scope>7TK</scope><scope>7TM</scope><scope>7U9</scope><scope>8FD</scope><scope>C1K</scope><scope>FR3</scope><scope>H94</scope><scope>M7N</scope><scope>P64</scope><scope>RC3</scope><scope>7X8</scope></search><sort><creationdate>20150601</creationdate><title>How to Study Adaptation (and Why To Do It That Way)</title><author>Olson, Mark E. ; Arroyo-Santos, Alfonso</author></sort><facets><frbrtype>5</frbrtype><frbrgroupid>cdi_FETCH-LOGICAL-c462t-40e614b591851d124ffd8d51bbabb19535da50c3cadbc2a536db5c525fb21ec13</frbrgroupid><rsrctype>articles</rsrctype><prefilter>articles</prefilter><language>eng</language><creationdate>2015</creationdate><topic>Adaptability</topic><topic>Adaptation, Physiological</topic><topic>Animals</topic><topic>Bayes Theorem</topic><topic>Biological adaptation</topic><topic>Biological Evolution</topic><topic>Biologists</topic><topic>Biology</topic><topic>Direct evidence</topic><topic>Ecological competition</topic><topic>Evolutionary biology</topic><topic>Heritability</topic><topic>Hypothetico deductive model</topic><topic>Phenotypic traits</topic><topic>Population characteristics</topic><topic>Reasoning</topic><toplevel>peer_reviewed</toplevel><toplevel>online_resources</toplevel><creatorcontrib>Olson, Mark E.</creatorcontrib><creatorcontrib>Arroyo-Santos, Alfonso</creatorcontrib><collection>Medline</collection><collection>MEDLINE</collection><collection>MEDLINE (Ovid)</collection><collection>MEDLINE</collection><collection>MEDLINE</collection><collection>PubMed</collection><collection>CrossRef</collection><collection>Animal Behavior Abstracts</collection><collection>Bacteriology Abstracts (Microbiology B)</collection><collection>Calcium & Calcified Tissue Abstracts</collection><collection>Chemoreception Abstracts</collection><collection>Ecology Abstracts</collection><collection>Entomology Abstracts (Full archive)</collection><collection>Industrial and Applied Microbiology Abstracts (Microbiology A)</collection><collection>Neurosciences Abstracts</collection><collection>Nucleic Acids Abstracts</collection><collection>Virology and AIDS Abstracts</collection><collection>Technology Research Database</collection><collection>Environmental Sciences and Pollution Management</collection><collection>Engineering Research Database</collection><collection>AIDS and Cancer Research Abstracts</collection><collection>Algology Mycology and Protozoology Abstracts (Microbiology C)</collection><collection>Biotechnology and BioEngineering Abstracts</collection><collection>Genetics Abstracts</collection><collection>MEDLINE - Academic</collection><jtitle>The Quarterly review of biology</jtitle></facets><delivery><delcategory>Remote Search Resource</delcategory><fulltext>fulltext</fulltext></delivery><addata><au>Olson, Mark E.</au><au>Arroyo-Santos, Alfonso</au><au>Handling Editor Daniel E. Dykhuizen</au><format>journal</format><genre>article</genre><ristype>JOUR</ristype><atitle>How to Study Adaptation (and Why To Do It That Way)</atitle><jtitle>The Quarterly review of biology</jtitle><addtitle>Q Rev Biol</addtitle><date>2015-06-01</date><risdate>2015</risdate><volume>90</volume><issue>2</issue><spage>167</spage><epage>191</epage><pages>167-191</pages><issn>0033-5770</issn><eissn>1539-7718</eissn><coden>QRBIAK</coden><abstract>Some adaptationist explanations are regarded as maximally solid and others fanciful just-so stories. Just-so stories are explanations based on very little evidence. Lack of evidence leads to circular-sounding reasoning: “this trait was shaped by selection in unseen ancestral populations and this selection must have occurred because the trait is present.” Well-supported adaptationist explanations include evidence that is not only abundant but selected from comparative, populational, and optimality perspectives, the three adaptationist subdisciplines. Each subdiscipline obtains its broad relevance in evolutionary biology via assumptions that can only be tested with the methods of the other subdisciplines. However, even in the best-supported explanations, assumptions regarding variation, heritability, and fitness in unseen ancestral populations are always present. These assumptions are accepted given how well they would explain the data if they were true. This means that some degree of “circularity” is present in all evolutionary explanations. Evolutionary explanation corresponds not to a deductive structure, as biologists usually assert, but instead to ones such as abduction or Bayesianism. With these structures in mind, we show the way to a healthier view of “circularity” in evolutionary biology and why integration across the comparative, populational, and optimality approaches is necessary.</abstract><cop>United States</cop><pub>The University of Chicago Press</pub><pmid>26285354</pmid><doi>10.1086/681438</doi><tpages>25</tpages><oa>free_for_read</oa></addata></record> |
fulltext | fulltext |
identifier | ISSN: 0033-5770 |
ispartof | The Quarterly review of biology, 2015-06, Vol.90 (2), p.167-191 |
issn | 0033-5770 1539-7718 |
language | eng |
recordid | cdi_proquest_miscellaneous_1705734807 |
source | Jstor Complete Legacy; MEDLINE |
subjects | Adaptability Adaptation, Physiological Animals Bayes Theorem Biological adaptation Biological Evolution Biologists Biology Direct evidence Ecological competition Evolutionary biology Heritability Hypothetico deductive model Phenotypic traits Population characteristics Reasoning |
title | How to Study Adaptation (and Why To Do It That Way) |
url | https://sfx.bib-bvb.de/sfx_tum?ctx_ver=Z39.88-2004&ctx_enc=info:ofi/enc:UTF-8&ctx_tim=2024-12-25T13%3A02%3A04IST&url_ver=Z39.88-2004&url_ctx_fmt=infofi/fmt:kev:mtx:ctx&rfr_id=info:sid/primo.exlibrisgroup.com:primo3-Article-jstor_proqu&rft_val_fmt=info:ofi/fmt:kev:mtx:journal&rft.genre=article&rft.atitle=How%20to%20Study%20Adaptation%20(and%20Why%20To%20Do%20It%20That%20Way)&rft.jtitle=The%20Quarterly%20review%20of%20biology&rft.au=Olson,%20Mark%20E.&rft.date=2015-06-01&rft.volume=90&rft.issue=2&rft.spage=167&rft.epage=191&rft.pages=167-191&rft.issn=0033-5770&rft.eissn=1539-7718&rft.coden=QRBIAK&rft_id=info:doi/10.1086/681438&rft_dat=%3Cjstor_proqu%3E10.1086/681438%3C/jstor_proqu%3E%3Curl%3E%3C/url%3E&disable_directlink=true&sfx.directlink=off&sfx.report_link=0&rft_id=info:oai/&rft_pqid=1683994477&rft_id=info:pmid/26285354&rft_jstor_id=10.1086/681438&rfr_iscdi=true |