Dreyfus on expertise: The limits of phenomenological analysis
Dreyfus's model of expert skill acquisition is philosophically important because it shifts the focus on expertise away from its social and technical externalization in STS, and its relegation to the historical and psychological context of discovery in the classical philosophy of science, to uni...
Gespeichert in:
Veröffentlicht in: | Continental philosophy review 2002-07, Vol.35 (3), p.245-279 |
---|---|
Hauptverfasser: | , |
Format: | Artikel |
Sprache: | eng |
Schlagworte: | |
Online-Zugang: | Volltext |
Tags: |
Tag hinzufügen
Keine Tags, Fügen Sie den ersten Tag hinzu!
|
container_end_page | 279 |
---|---|
container_issue | 3 |
container_start_page | 245 |
container_title | Continental philosophy review |
container_volume | 35 |
creator | SELINGER, Evan M CREASE, Robert P |
description | Dreyfus's model of expert skill acquisition is philosophically important because it shifts the focus on expertise away from its social and technical externalization in STS, and its relegation to the historical and psychological context of discovery in the classical philosophy of science, to universal structures of embodied cognition and affect. In doing so he explains why experts are not best described as ideologues and why their authority is not exclusively based on social networking. Moreover, by phenomenologically analyzing expertise from a first person perspective, he reveals the limitations of, and sometimes superficial treatment that comes from, investigating expertise from a third person perspective. Thus, he shows that expertise is a prime example of a subject that is essential to science but can only be fully elaborated with the aid of phenomenological tools. However, both Dreyfus's descriptive model and his normative claims are flawed due to the lack of hermeneutical sensitivity. He assumes an expert's knowledge has crystallized out of contextual sensitivity plus experience, and that an expert has shed, during the training process, whatever prejudices, ideologies, hidden agendas, or other forms of cultural embeddedness, that person might have begun with. One would never imagine, from Dreyfus's account, that society could possibly be endangered by experts, only how society's expectations and actions could endanger experts. The stories of actual controversies not only shows things do not work the way Dreyfus claims, but also that it would be less salutary if they did. Such stories amount to counterexamples to Dreyfus's normative claims, and point to serious shortcomings in his arguments.[PUBLICATION ABSTRACT] |
doi_str_mv | 10.1023/A:1022643708111 |
format | Article |
fullrecord | <record><control><sourceid>proquest_pasca</sourceid><recordid>TN_cdi_proquest_journals_753970608</recordid><sourceformat>XML</sourceformat><sourcesystem>PC</sourcesystem><sourcerecordid>2146039191</sourcerecordid><originalsourceid>FETCH-LOGICAL-p212t-8dc4d138791e611f09fa5355d80a20963f0dbdd95b8d3f61eac30617bcb3e12f3</originalsourceid><addsrcrecordid>eNotjk1Lw0AYhBdRsFbPXoPgMfq-u9mPFDyU1i8oeKnnsMnu2i1pEndTMP_eFXsYZmCG4SHkFuEBgbLH5SIZFQWToBDxjMyQS5YjAjtPmSmZU1XQS3IV4x4AkUM5I0_rYCd3jFnfZfZnsGH00S6y7c5mrT_4MRUuG3a26w9Jbf_lG91mutPtFH28JhdOt9HenHxOPl-et6u3fPPx-r5abvKBIh1zZZrC_BGUaAWig9Jpzjg3CjSFUjAHpjam5LUyzAm0umEgUNZNzSxSx-bk7v93CP330cax2vfHkCBiJTkrJQhQaXR_GumYIF3QXeNjNQR_0GGqsBBcKCnZLwBPVsE</addsrcrecordid><sourcetype>Aggregation Database</sourcetype><iscdi>true</iscdi><recordtype>article</recordtype><pqid>753970608</pqid></control><display><type>article</type><title>Dreyfus on expertise: The limits of phenomenological analysis</title><source>SpringerLink Journals - AutoHoldings</source><creator>SELINGER, Evan M ; CREASE, Robert P</creator><creatorcontrib>SELINGER, Evan M ; CREASE, Robert P</creatorcontrib><description>Dreyfus's model of expert skill acquisition is philosophically important because it shifts the focus on expertise away from its social and technical externalization in STS, and its relegation to the historical and psychological context of discovery in the classical philosophy of science, to universal structures of embodied cognition and affect. In doing so he explains why experts are not best described as ideologues and why their authority is not exclusively based on social networking. Moreover, by phenomenologically analyzing expertise from a first person perspective, he reveals the limitations of, and sometimes superficial treatment that comes from, investigating expertise from a third person perspective. Thus, he shows that expertise is a prime example of a subject that is essential to science but can only be fully elaborated with the aid of phenomenological tools. However, both Dreyfus's descriptive model and his normative claims are flawed due to the lack of hermeneutical sensitivity. He assumes an expert's knowledge has crystallized out of contextual sensitivity plus experience, and that an expert has shed, during the training process, whatever prejudices, ideologies, hidden agendas, or other forms of cultural embeddedness, that person might have begun with. One would never imagine, from Dreyfus's account, that society could possibly be endangered by experts, only how society's expectations and actions could endanger experts. The stories of actual controversies not only shows things do not work the way Dreyfus claims, but also that it would be less salutary if they did. Such stories amount to counterexamples to Dreyfus's normative claims, and point to serious shortcomings in his arguments.[PUBLICATION ABSTRACT]</description><identifier>ISSN: 1387-2842</identifier><identifier>EISSN: 1573-1103</identifier><identifier>DOI: 10.1023/A:1022643708111</identifier><language>eng</language><publisher>Dordrecht: Springer</publisher><subject>Epistemology. Philosophy of science. Theory of knowledge ; Experts ; Philosophy</subject><ispartof>Continental philosophy review, 2002-07, Vol.35 (3), p.245-279</ispartof><rights>2003 INIST-CNRS</rights><rights>Kluwer Academic Publishers 2002</rights><lds50>peer_reviewed</lds50><woscitedreferencessubscribed>false</woscitedreferencessubscribed></display><links><openurl>$$Topenurl_article</openurl><openurlfulltext>$$Topenurlfull_article</openurlfulltext><thumbnail>$$Tsyndetics_thumb_exl</thumbnail><link.rule.ids>314,780,784,27923,27924</link.rule.ids><backlink>$$Uhttp://pascal-francis.inist.fr/vibad/index.php?action=getRecordDetail&idt=14656877$$DView record in Pascal Francis$$Hfree_for_read</backlink></links><search><creatorcontrib>SELINGER, Evan M</creatorcontrib><creatorcontrib>CREASE, Robert P</creatorcontrib><title>Dreyfus on expertise: The limits of phenomenological analysis</title><title>Continental philosophy review</title><description>Dreyfus's model of expert skill acquisition is philosophically important because it shifts the focus on expertise away from its social and technical externalization in STS, and its relegation to the historical and psychological context of discovery in the classical philosophy of science, to universal structures of embodied cognition and affect. In doing so he explains why experts are not best described as ideologues and why their authority is not exclusively based on social networking. Moreover, by phenomenologically analyzing expertise from a first person perspective, he reveals the limitations of, and sometimes superficial treatment that comes from, investigating expertise from a third person perspective. Thus, he shows that expertise is a prime example of a subject that is essential to science but can only be fully elaborated with the aid of phenomenological tools. However, both Dreyfus's descriptive model and his normative claims are flawed due to the lack of hermeneutical sensitivity. He assumes an expert's knowledge has crystallized out of contextual sensitivity plus experience, and that an expert has shed, during the training process, whatever prejudices, ideologies, hidden agendas, or other forms of cultural embeddedness, that person might have begun with. One would never imagine, from Dreyfus's account, that society could possibly be endangered by experts, only how society's expectations and actions could endanger experts. The stories of actual controversies not only shows things do not work the way Dreyfus claims, but also that it would be less salutary if they did. Such stories amount to counterexamples to Dreyfus's normative claims, and point to serious shortcomings in his arguments.[PUBLICATION ABSTRACT]</description><subject>Epistemology. Philosophy of science. Theory of knowledge</subject><subject>Experts</subject><subject>Philosophy</subject><issn>1387-2842</issn><issn>1573-1103</issn><fulltext>true</fulltext><rsrctype>article</rsrctype><creationdate>2002</creationdate><recordtype>article</recordtype><sourceid>88H</sourceid><sourceid>ABUWG</sourceid><sourceid>AFKRA</sourceid><sourceid>AVQMV</sourceid><sourceid>AZQEC</sourceid><sourceid>BENPR</sourceid><sourceid>CCPQU</sourceid><sourceid>DWQXO</sourceid><sourceid>GNUQQ</sourceid><sourceid>K50</sourceid><sourceid>M1D</sourceid><sourceid>M2N</sourceid><recordid>eNotjk1Lw0AYhBdRsFbPXoPgMfq-u9mPFDyU1i8oeKnnsMnu2i1pEndTMP_eFXsYZmCG4SHkFuEBgbLH5SIZFQWToBDxjMyQS5YjAjtPmSmZU1XQS3IV4x4AkUM5I0_rYCd3jFnfZfZnsGH00S6y7c5mrT_4MRUuG3a26w9Jbf_lG91mutPtFH28JhdOt9HenHxOPl-et6u3fPPx-r5abvKBIh1zZZrC_BGUaAWig9Jpzjg3CjSFUjAHpjam5LUyzAm0umEgUNZNzSxSx-bk7v93CP330cax2vfHkCBiJTkrJQhQaXR_GumYIF3QXeNjNQR_0GGqsBBcKCnZLwBPVsE</recordid><startdate>20020701</startdate><enddate>20020701</enddate><creator>SELINGER, Evan M</creator><creator>CREASE, Robert P</creator><general>Springer</general><general>Springer Nature B.V</general><scope>IQODW</scope><scope>3V.</scope><scope>7XB</scope><scope>88H</scope><scope>8FK</scope><scope>AABKS</scope><scope>ABSDQ</scope><scope>ABUWG</scope><scope>AFKRA</scope><scope>AVQMV</scope><scope>AZQEC</scope><scope>BENPR</scope><scope>CCPQU</scope><scope>DWQXO</scope><scope>GB0</scope><scope>GNUQQ</scope><scope>K50</scope><scope>M1D</scope><scope>M2N</scope><scope>PQEST</scope><scope>PQQKQ</scope><scope>PQUKI</scope><scope>PRINS</scope><scope>Q9U</scope></search><sort><creationdate>20020701</creationdate><title>Dreyfus on expertise: The limits of phenomenological analysis</title><author>SELINGER, Evan M ; CREASE, Robert P</author></sort><facets><frbrtype>5</frbrtype><frbrgroupid>cdi_FETCH-LOGICAL-p212t-8dc4d138791e611f09fa5355d80a20963f0dbdd95b8d3f61eac30617bcb3e12f3</frbrgroupid><rsrctype>articles</rsrctype><prefilter>articles</prefilter><language>eng</language><creationdate>2002</creationdate><topic>Epistemology. Philosophy of science. Theory of knowledge</topic><topic>Experts</topic><topic>Philosophy</topic><toplevel>peer_reviewed</toplevel><toplevel>online_resources</toplevel><creatorcontrib>SELINGER, Evan M</creatorcontrib><creatorcontrib>CREASE, Robert P</creatorcontrib><collection>Pascal-Francis</collection><collection>ProQuest Central (Corporate)</collection><collection>ProQuest Central (purchase pre-March 2016)</collection><collection>Religion Database (Alumni Edition)</collection><collection>ProQuest Central (Alumni) (purchase pre-March 2016)</collection><collection>Philosophy Collection</collection><collection>Philosophy Database</collection><collection>ProQuest Central (Alumni Edition)</collection><collection>ProQuest Central UK/Ireland</collection><collection>Arts Premium Collection</collection><collection>ProQuest Central Essentials</collection><collection>ProQuest Central</collection><collection>ProQuest One Community College</collection><collection>ProQuest Central Korea</collection><collection>DELNET Social Sciences & Humanities Collection</collection><collection>ProQuest Central Student</collection><collection>Art, Design & Architecture Collection</collection><collection>Arts & Humanities Database</collection><collection>Religion Database</collection><collection>ProQuest One Academic Eastern Edition (DO NOT USE)</collection><collection>ProQuest One Academic</collection><collection>ProQuest One Academic UKI Edition</collection><collection>ProQuest Central China</collection><collection>ProQuest Central Basic</collection><jtitle>Continental philosophy review</jtitle></facets><delivery><delcategory>Remote Search Resource</delcategory><fulltext>fulltext</fulltext></delivery><addata><au>SELINGER, Evan M</au><au>CREASE, Robert P</au><format>journal</format><genre>article</genre><ristype>JOUR</ristype><atitle>Dreyfus on expertise: The limits of phenomenological analysis</atitle><jtitle>Continental philosophy review</jtitle><date>2002-07-01</date><risdate>2002</risdate><volume>35</volume><issue>3</issue><spage>245</spage><epage>279</epage><pages>245-279</pages><issn>1387-2842</issn><eissn>1573-1103</eissn><abstract>Dreyfus's model of expert skill acquisition is philosophically important because it shifts the focus on expertise away from its social and technical externalization in STS, and its relegation to the historical and psychological context of discovery in the classical philosophy of science, to universal structures of embodied cognition and affect. In doing so he explains why experts are not best described as ideologues and why their authority is not exclusively based on social networking. Moreover, by phenomenologically analyzing expertise from a first person perspective, he reveals the limitations of, and sometimes superficial treatment that comes from, investigating expertise from a third person perspective. Thus, he shows that expertise is a prime example of a subject that is essential to science but can only be fully elaborated with the aid of phenomenological tools. However, both Dreyfus's descriptive model and his normative claims are flawed due to the lack of hermeneutical sensitivity. He assumes an expert's knowledge has crystallized out of contextual sensitivity plus experience, and that an expert has shed, during the training process, whatever prejudices, ideologies, hidden agendas, or other forms of cultural embeddedness, that person might have begun with. One would never imagine, from Dreyfus's account, that society could possibly be endangered by experts, only how society's expectations and actions could endanger experts. The stories of actual controversies not only shows things do not work the way Dreyfus claims, but also that it would be less salutary if they did. Such stories amount to counterexamples to Dreyfus's normative claims, and point to serious shortcomings in his arguments.[PUBLICATION ABSTRACT]</abstract><cop>Dordrecht</cop><pub>Springer</pub><doi>10.1023/A:1022643708111</doi><tpages>35</tpages></addata></record> |
fulltext | fulltext |
identifier | ISSN: 1387-2842 |
ispartof | Continental philosophy review, 2002-07, Vol.35 (3), p.245-279 |
issn | 1387-2842 1573-1103 |
language | eng |
recordid | cdi_proquest_journals_753970608 |
source | SpringerLink Journals - AutoHoldings |
subjects | Epistemology. Philosophy of science. Theory of knowledge Experts Philosophy |
title | Dreyfus on expertise: The limits of phenomenological analysis |
url | https://sfx.bib-bvb.de/sfx_tum?ctx_ver=Z39.88-2004&ctx_enc=info:ofi/enc:UTF-8&ctx_tim=2025-01-11T21%3A13%3A59IST&url_ver=Z39.88-2004&url_ctx_fmt=infofi/fmt:kev:mtx:ctx&rfr_id=info:sid/primo.exlibrisgroup.com:primo3-Article-proquest_pasca&rft_val_fmt=info:ofi/fmt:kev:mtx:journal&rft.genre=article&rft.atitle=Dreyfus%20on%20expertise:%20The%20limits%20of%20phenomenological%20analysis&rft.jtitle=Continental%20philosophy%20review&rft.au=SELINGER,%20Evan%20M&rft.date=2002-07-01&rft.volume=35&rft.issue=3&rft.spage=245&rft.epage=279&rft.pages=245-279&rft.issn=1387-2842&rft.eissn=1573-1103&rft_id=info:doi/10.1023/A:1022643708111&rft_dat=%3Cproquest_pasca%3E2146039191%3C/proquest_pasca%3E%3Curl%3E%3C/url%3E&disable_directlink=true&sfx.directlink=off&sfx.report_link=0&rft_id=info:oai/&rft_pqid=753970608&rft_id=info:pmid/&rfr_iscdi=true |