ACTS OF THOUGHT AND RE‐ENACTMENT IN COLLINGWOOD'S PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY
ABSTRACT This article explores one of Collingwood's most puzzling claims—that, in re‐enacting a past act of thought, I can revive not just the propositional content of that act but also the very act of thought itself. This aspect of Collingwood's ideas has been largely ignored, and, when n...
Gespeichert in:
Veröffentlicht in: | History and theory :Studies in the philosophy of history 2024-03, Vol.63 (1), p.94-111 |
---|---|
1. Verfasser: | |
Format: | Artikel |
Sprache: | eng |
Schlagworte: | |
Online-Zugang: | Volltext |
Tags: |
Tag hinzufügen
Keine Tags, Fügen Sie den ersten Tag hinzu!
|
container_end_page | 111 |
---|---|
container_issue | 1 |
container_start_page | 94 |
container_title | History and theory :Studies in the philosophy of history |
container_volume | 63 |
creator | ROBSON, MARK IAN THOMAS |
description | ABSTRACT
This article explores one of Collingwood's most puzzling claims—that, in re‐enacting a past act of thought, I can revive not just the propositional content of that act but also the very act of thought itself. This aspect of Collingwood's ideas has been largely ignored, and, when not ignored, it has been almost universally rejected. After all, we might ask, how can it be that two acts of thought—one, say, had by Carol in the library on Wednesday and another act of thought had by Harold in his study on Thursday—are literally identical? I explore this baffling claim and, in particular, Collingwood's argument that acts of thought can have the identity of a continuant. I try to show how the idea of the identity of the continuant might be used to remove some of the puzzlement in Collingwood's claim about literal identity between acts of thought; I thus show how Harold, on Thursday, might be able to experience the exact same act of thought that Carol had on Wednesday. |
doi_str_mv | 10.1111/hith.12335 |
format | Article |
fullrecord | <record><control><sourceid>proquest_cross</sourceid><recordid>TN_cdi_proquest_journals_2932292591</recordid><sourceformat>XML</sourceformat><sourcesystem>PC</sourcesystem><sourcerecordid>2932292591</sourcerecordid><originalsourceid>FETCH-LOGICAL-c2605-725745c2c76ca16bda3c42b2193aed999f46a1413e612ce9ef124531807e80d13</originalsourceid><addsrcrecordid>eNp9kMFKw0AQhhdRsFYvPkHAgyCk7swmm-6xpGk3ELOlSZGeljTd0JZqa9JSevMRfEafxMR4di4zw3z_P_ATcg-0B3U9r9aHVQ-QMfeCdMDhfRsZZZekQynUM3f5Nbmpqg2td6TYIeHATxNLjaxUqtlYptYgHlrT4PvzK4jr00sQp1YYW76KojAevyo1fEysiQwjlaiJnDdKGSapms5vyVWRbStz99e7ZDYKUl_akRqH_iCyc-TUtT10PcfNMfd4ngFfLDOWO7hAECwzSyFE4fAMHGCGA-ZGmALQcRn0qWf6dAmsSx5a3325-zia6qA3u2P5Xr_UKBiiQFc01FNL5eWuqkpT6H25fsvKswaqm6h0E5X-jaqGoYVP6605_0NqGaay1fwAb81kSw</addsrcrecordid><sourcetype>Aggregation Database</sourcetype><iscdi>true</iscdi><recordtype>article</recordtype><pqid>2932292591</pqid></control><display><type>article</type><title>ACTS OF THOUGHT AND RE‐ENACTMENT IN COLLINGWOOD'S PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY</title><source>Wiley Journals</source><creator>ROBSON, MARK IAN THOMAS</creator><creatorcontrib>ROBSON, MARK IAN THOMAS</creatorcontrib><description>ABSTRACT
This article explores one of Collingwood's most puzzling claims—that, in re‐enacting a past act of thought, I can revive not just the propositional content of that act but also the very act of thought itself. This aspect of Collingwood's ideas has been largely ignored, and, when not ignored, it has been almost universally rejected. After all, we might ask, how can it be that two acts of thought—one, say, had by Carol in the library on Wednesday and another act of thought had by Harold in his study on Thursday—are literally identical? I explore this baffling claim and, in particular, Collingwood's argument that acts of thought can have the identity of a continuant. I try to show how the idea of the identity of the continuant might be used to remove some of the puzzlement in Collingwood's claim about literal identity between acts of thought; I thus show how Harold, on Thursday, might be able to experience the exact same act of thought that Carol had on Wednesday.</description><identifier>ISSN: 0018-2656</identifier><identifier>EISSN: 1468-2303</identifier><identifier>DOI: 10.1111/hith.12335</identifier><language>eng</language><publisher>Oxford: Blackwell Publishing Ltd</publisher><subject>acts of thought ; Collingwood, R G (Robin George) (1889-1943) ; Critical thinking ; Enactment ; History ; Identity ; identity of the continuant ; Philosophy of history ; re‐enactment</subject><ispartof>History and theory :Studies in the philosophy of history, 2024-03, Vol.63 (1), p.94-111</ispartof><rights>2023 Wesleyan University.</rights><rights>2024 Wesleyan University.</rights><lds50>peer_reviewed</lds50><woscitedreferencessubscribed>false</woscitedreferencessubscribed></display><links><openurl>$$Topenurl_article</openurl><openurlfulltext>$$Topenurlfull_article</openurlfulltext><thumbnail>$$Tsyndetics_thumb_exl</thumbnail><linktopdf>$$Uhttps://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/pdf/10.1111%2Fhith.12335$$EPDF$$P50$$Gwiley$$H</linktopdf><linktohtml>$$Uhttps://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/full/10.1111%2Fhith.12335$$EHTML$$P50$$Gwiley$$H</linktohtml><link.rule.ids>314,780,784,1417,27924,27925,45574,45575</link.rule.ids></links><search><creatorcontrib>ROBSON, MARK IAN THOMAS</creatorcontrib><title>ACTS OF THOUGHT AND RE‐ENACTMENT IN COLLINGWOOD'S PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY</title><title>History and theory :Studies in the philosophy of history</title><description>ABSTRACT
This article explores one of Collingwood's most puzzling claims—that, in re‐enacting a past act of thought, I can revive not just the propositional content of that act but also the very act of thought itself. This aspect of Collingwood's ideas has been largely ignored, and, when not ignored, it has been almost universally rejected. After all, we might ask, how can it be that two acts of thought—one, say, had by Carol in the library on Wednesday and another act of thought had by Harold in his study on Thursday—are literally identical? I explore this baffling claim and, in particular, Collingwood's argument that acts of thought can have the identity of a continuant. I try to show how the idea of the identity of the continuant might be used to remove some of the puzzlement in Collingwood's claim about literal identity between acts of thought; I thus show how Harold, on Thursday, might be able to experience the exact same act of thought that Carol had on Wednesday.</description><subject>acts of thought</subject><subject>Collingwood, R G (Robin George) (1889-1943)</subject><subject>Critical thinking</subject><subject>Enactment</subject><subject>History</subject><subject>Identity</subject><subject>identity of the continuant</subject><subject>Philosophy of history</subject><subject>re‐enactment</subject><issn>0018-2656</issn><issn>1468-2303</issn><fulltext>true</fulltext><rsrctype>article</rsrctype><creationdate>2024</creationdate><recordtype>article</recordtype><recordid>eNp9kMFKw0AQhhdRsFYvPkHAgyCk7swmm-6xpGk3ELOlSZGeljTd0JZqa9JSevMRfEafxMR4di4zw3z_P_ATcg-0B3U9r9aHVQ-QMfeCdMDhfRsZZZekQynUM3f5Nbmpqg2td6TYIeHATxNLjaxUqtlYptYgHlrT4PvzK4jr00sQp1YYW76KojAevyo1fEysiQwjlaiJnDdKGSapms5vyVWRbStz99e7ZDYKUl_akRqH_iCyc-TUtT10PcfNMfd4ngFfLDOWO7hAECwzSyFE4fAMHGCGA-ZGmALQcRn0qWf6dAmsSx5a3325-zia6qA3u2P5Xr_UKBiiQFc01FNL5eWuqkpT6H25fsvKswaqm6h0E5X-jaqGoYVP6605_0NqGaay1fwAb81kSw</recordid><startdate>202403</startdate><enddate>202403</enddate><creator>ROBSON, MARK IAN THOMAS</creator><general>Blackwell Publishing Ltd</general><scope>AAYXX</scope><scope>CITATION</scope><scope>8BJ</scope><scope>FQK</scope><scope>JBE</scope></search><sort><creationdate>202403</creationdate><title>ACTS OF THOUGHT AND RE‐ENACTMENT IN COLLINGWOOD'S PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY</title><author>ROBSON, MARK IAN THOMAS</author></sort><facets><frbrtype>5</frbrtype><frbrgroupid>cdi_FETCH-LOGICAL-c2605-725745c2c76ca16bda3c42b2193aed999f46a1413e612ce9ef124531807e80d13</frbrgroupid><rsrctype>articles</rsrctype><prefilter>articles</prefilter><language>eng</language><creationdate>2024</creationdate><topic>acts of thought</topic><topic>Collingwood, R G (Robin George) (1889-1943)</topic><topic>Critical thinking</topic><topic>Enactment</topic><topic>History</topic><topic>Identity</topic><topic>identity of the continuant</topic><topic>Philosophy of history</topic><topic>re‐enactment</topic><toplevel>peer_reviewed</toplevel><toplevel>online_resources</toplevel><creatorcontrib>ROBSON, MARK IAN THOMAS</creatorcontrib><collection>CrossRef</collection><collection>International Bibliography of the Social Sciences (IBSS)</collection><collection>International Bibliography of the Social Sciences</collection><collection>International Bibliography of the Social Sciences</collection><jtitle>History and theory :Studies in the philosophy of history</jtitle></facets><delivery><delcategory>Remote Search Resource</delcategory><fulltext>fulltext</fulltext></delivery><addata><au>ROBSON, MARK IAN THOMAS</au><format>journal</format><genre>article</genre><ristype>JOUR</ristype><atitle>ACTS OF THOUGHT AND RE‐ENACTMENT IN COLLINGWOOD'S PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY</atitle><jtitle>History and theory :Studies in the philosophy of history</jtitle><date>2024-03</date><risdate>2024</risdate><volume>63</volume><issue>1</issue><spage>94</spage><epage>111</epage><pages>94-111</pages><issn>0018-2656</issn><eissn>1468-2303</eissn><abstract>ABSTRACT
This article explores one of Collingwood's most puzzling claims—that, in re‐enacting a past act of thought, I can revive not just the propositional content of that act but also the very act of thought itself. This aspect of Collingwood's ideas has been largely ignored, and, when not ignored, it has been almost universally rejected. After all, we might ask, how can it be that two acts of thought—one, say, had by Carol in the library on Wednesday and another act of thought had by Harold in his study on Thursday—are literally identical? I explore this baffling claim and, in particular, Collingwood's argument that acts of thought can have the identity of a continuant. I try to show how the idea of the identity of the continuant might be used to remove some of the puzzlement in Collingwood's claim about literal identity between acts of thought; I thus show how Harold, on Thursday, might be able to experience the exact same act of thought that Carol had on Wednesday.</abstract><cop>Oxford</cop><pub>Blackwell Publishing Ltd</pub><doi>10.1111/hith.12335</doi><tpages>18</tpages></addata></record> |
fulltext | fulltext |
identifier | ISSN: 0018-2656 |
ispartof | History and theory :Studies in the philosophy of history, 2024-03, Vol.63 (1), p.94-111 |
issn | 0018-2656 1468-2303 |
language | eng |
recordid | cdi_proquest_journals_2932292591 |
source | Wiley Journals |
subjects | acts of thought Collingwood, R G (Robin George) (1889-1943) Critical thinking Enactment History Identity identity of the continuant Philosophy of history re‐enactment |
title | ACTS OF THOUGHT AND RE‐ENACTMENT IN COLLINGWOOD'S PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY |
url | https://sfx.bib-bvb.de/sfx_tum?ctx_ver=Z39.88-2004&ctx_enc=info:ofi/enc:UTF-8&ctx_tim=2025-01-04T00%3A21%3A54IST&url_ver=Z39.88-2004&url_ctx_fmt=infofi/fmt:kev:mtx:ctx&rfr_id=info:sid/primo.exlibrisgroup.com:primo3-Article-proquest_cross&rft_val_fmt=info:ofi/fmt:kev:mtx:journal&rft.genre=article&rft.atitle=ACTS%20OF%20THOUGHT%20AND%20RE%E2%80%90ENACTMENT%20IN%20COLLINGWOOD'S%20PHILOSOPHY%20OF%20HISTORY&rft.jtitle=History%20and%20theory%20:Studies%20in%20the%20philosophy%20of%20history&rft.au=ROBSON,%20MARK%20IAN%20THOMAS&rft.date=2024-03&rft.volume=63&rft.issue=1&rft.spage=94&rft.epage=111&rft.pages=94-111&rft.issn=0018-2656&rft.eissn=1468-2303&rft_id=info:doi/10.1111/hith.12335&rft_dat=%3Cproquest_cross%3E2932292591%3C/proquest_cross%3E%3Curl%3E%3C/url%3E&disable_directlink=true&sfx.directlink=off&sfx.report_link=0&rft_id=info:oai/&rft_pqid=2932292591&rft_id=info:pmid/&rfr_iscdi=true |