Overcoming the underdetermination of specimens

Philosophers of science are well aware that theories are underdetermined by data. But what about the data? Scientific data are selected and processed representations or pieces of nature. What is useless context and what is valuable specimen, as well as how specimens are processed for study, are not...

Ausführliche Beschreibung

Gespeichert in:
Bibliographische Detailangaben
Veröffentlicht in:Biology & philosophy 2019-04, Vol.34 (2), p.1-18, Article 24
1. Verfasser: Wylie, Caitlin Donahue
Format: Artikel
Sprache:eng
Schlagworte:
Online-Zugang:Volltext
Tags: Tag hinzufügen
Keine Tags, Fügen Sie den ersten Tag hinzu!
container_end_page 18
container_issue 2
container_start_page 1
container_title Biology & philosophy
container_volume 34
creator Wylie, Caitlin Donahue
description Philosophers of science are well aware that theories are underdetermined by data. But what about the data? Scientific data are selected and processed representations or pieces of nature. What is useless context and what is valuable specimen, as well as how specimens are processed for study, are not obvious or predetermined givens. Instead, they are decisions made by scientists and other research workers, such as technicians, that produce different outcomes for the data. Vertebrate fossils provide a revealing case of this data-processing, because they are embedded in rock that often matches the fossils’ color and texture, requiring an expert eye to judge where the fossil/context interface is. Fossil preparators then permanently define this interface by chiseling away the material they identify as rock. As a result, fossil specimens can emerge in multiple possible forms depending on the preparator’s judgment, skill, and chosen tools. A prepared fossil then is not yet data but potential data, following Leonelli’s (Philos Sci 82:810–821, 2015 . https://doi.org/10.1086/684083 ) relational framework in which data are defined as evidence that scientists have used to support a proposed theory. This paper draws on ethnographic evidence to assess how scientists overcome this underdetermination of specimens, as potential data, in addition to the underdetermination of theories and of data, to successfully construct specimen-based knowledge. Among other strategies, paleontology maintains a division of labor between data-makers and theory-makers. This distinction serves to justify the omission of preparators’ nonstandard, individualized techniques from scientific publications. This separation has benefits for both scientists and technicians; however, it restricts knowledge production by preventing scientists from understanding how the pieces of nature they study were processed into researchable specimens.
doi_str_mv 10.1007/s10539-019-9674-2
format Article
fullrecord <record><control><sourceid>gale_proqu</sourceid><recordid>TN_cdi_proquest_journals_2202712620</recordid><sourceformat>XML</sourceformat><sourcesystem>PC</sourcesystem><galeid>A581224441</galeid><sourcerecordid>A581224441</sourcerecordid><originalsourceid>FETCH-LOGICAL-c491t-4014b80ecedc6dd4eb5afc800b916cad7216d54fc530193e89e982b3719bfbdc3</originalsourceid><addsrcrecordid>eNp1kctKAzEUhoMoWKsP4K4gCC6mnmQylyxL8VIoCF7WIZOcaad0JjXJiL69KRVqQckicPi-XP6fkEsKYwpQ3HoKWSoSoCIRecETdkQGNCtYUnLgx2QANBdJWubFKTnzfgUAOed0QMZPH-i0bZtuMQpLHPWdQWcwoIsjFRrbjWw98hvUTYudPycntVp7vPjZh-Tt_u51-pjMnx5m08k80VzQkHCgvCoBNRqdG8OxylStS4BK0FwrUzCam4zXOkvji1MsBYqSVWlBRVVXRqdDcrU7d-Pse48-yJXtXRevlIwBKyjLGeyphVqjbLraBqd023gtJ1lJGePxj5Ea_0HFZbBttO2wbuL8QLg5ECIT8DMsVO-9nL08H7LXv9glqnVYervut8n5Q5DuQO2s9w5ruXFNq9yXpCC3FcpdhTIGIrcVShYdtnN8ZLsFun0K_0vfQ-yatA</addsrcrecordid><sourcetype>Aggregation Database</sourcetype><iscdi>true</iscdi><recordtype>article</recordtype><pqid>2202712620</pqid></control><display><type>article</type><title>Overcoming the underdetermination of specimens</title><source>SpringerNature Journals</source><creator>Wylie, Caitlin Donahue</creator><creatorcontrib>Wylie, Caitlin Donahue</creatorcontrib><description>Philosophers of science are well aware that theories are underdetermined by data. But what about the data? Scientific data are selected and processed representations or pieces of nature. What is useless context and what is valuable specimen, as well as how specimens are processed for study, are not obvious or predetermined givens. Instead, they are decisions made by scientists and other research workers, such as technicians, that produce different outcomes for the data. Vertebrate fossils provide a revealing case of this data-processing, because they are embedded in rock that often matches the fossils’ color and texture, requiring an expert eye to judge where the fossil/context interface is. Fossil preparators then permanently define this interface by chiseling away the material they identify as rock. As a result, fossil specimens can emerge in multiple possible forms depending on the preparator’s judgment, skill, and chosen tools. A prepared fossil then is not yet data but potential data, following Leonelli’s (Philos Sci 82:810–821, 2015 . https://doi.org/10.1086/684083 ) relational framework in which data are defined as evidence that scientists have used to support a proposed theory. This paper draws on ethnographic evidence to assess how scientists overcome this underdetermination of specimens, as potential data, in addition to the underdetermination of theories and of data, to successfully construct specimen-based knowledge. Among other strategies, paleontology maintains a division of labor between data-makers and theory-makers. This distinction serves to justify the omission of preparators’ nonstandard, individualized techniques from scientific publications. This separation has benefits for both scientists and technicians; however, it restricts knowledge production by preventing scientists from understanding how the pieces of nature they study were processed into researchable specimens.</description><identifier>ISSN: 0169-3867</identifier><identifier>EISSN: 1572-8404</identifier><identifier>DOI: 10.1007/s10539-019-9674-2</identifier><language>eng</language><publisher>Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands</publisher><subject>Archaeology ; Data processing ; Division of labor ; Education ; Evolutionary Biology ; Fossils ; Material culture ; Paleobiology and Philosophy ; Paleontology ; Philosophers ; Philosophy ; Philosophy of Biology ; Retirement benefits ; Scientific method ; Scientists ; Training ; Workers</subject><ispartof>Biology &amp; philosophy, 2019-04, Vol.34 (2), p.1-18, Article 24</ispartof><rights>Springer Nature B.V. 2019</rights><rights>COPYRIGHT 2019 Springer</rights><rights>Biology &amp; Philosophy is a copyright of Springer, (2019). All Rights Reserved.</rights><lds50>peer_reviewed</lds50><oa>free_for_read</oa><woscitedreferencessubscribed>false</woscitedreferencessubscribed><citedby>FETCH-LOGICAL-c491t-4014b80ecedc6dd4eb5afc800b916cad7216d54fc530193e89e982b3719bfbdc3</citedby><cites>FETCH-LOGICAL-c491t-4014b80ecedc6dd4eb5afc800b916cad7216d54fc530193e89e982b3719bfbdc3</cites><orcidid>0000-0002-0214-7837</orcidid></display><links><openurl>$$Topenurl_article</openurl><openurlfulltext>$$Topenurlfull_article</openurlfulltext><thumbnail>$$Tsyndetics_thumb_exl</thumbnail><linktopdf>$$Uhttps://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/s10539-019-9674-2$$EPDF$$P50$$Gspringer$$H</linktopdf><linktohtml>$$Uhttps://link.springer.com/10.1007/s10539-019-9674-2$$EHTML$$P50$$Gspringer$$H</linktohtml><link.rule.ids>315,782,786,27933,27934,41497,42566,51328</link.rule.ids></links><search><creatorcontrib>Wylie, Caitlin Donahue</creatorcontrib><title>Overcoming the underdetermination of specimens</title><title>Biology &amp; philosophy</title><addtitle>Biol Philos</addtitle><description>Philosophers of science are well aware that theories are underdetermined by data. But what about the data? Scientific data are selected and processed representations or pieces of nature. What is useless context and what is valuable specimen, as well as how specimens are processed for study, are not obvious or predetermined givens. Instead, they are decisions made by scientists and other research workers, such as technicians, that produce different outcomes for the data. Vertebrate fossils provide a revealing case of this data-processing, because they are embedded in rock that often matches the fossils’ color and texture, requiring an expert eye to judge where the fossil/context interface is. Fossil preparators then permanently define this interface by chiseling away the material they identify as rock. As a result, fossil specimens can emerge in multiple possible forms depending on the preparator’s judgment, skill, and chosen tools. A prepared fossil then is not yet data but potential data, following Leonelli’s (Philos Sci 82:810–821, 2015 . https://doi.org/10.1086/684083 ) relational framework in which data are defined as evidence that scientists have used to support a proposed theory. This paper draws on ethnographic evidence to assess how scientists overcome this underdetermination of specimens, as potential data, in addition to the underdetermination of theories and of data, to successfully construct specimen-based knowledge. Among other strategies, paleontology maintains a division of labor between data-makers and theory-makers. This distinction serves to justify the omission of preparators’ nonstandard, individualized techniques from scientific publications. This separation has benefits for both scientists and technicians; however, it restricts knowledge production by preventing scientists from understanding how the pieces of nature they study were processed into researchable specimens.</description><subject>Archaeology</subject><subject>Data processing</subject><subject>Division of labor</subject><subject>Education</subject><subject>Evolutionary Biology</subject><subject>Fossils</subject><subject>Material culture</subject><subject>Paleobiology and Philosophy</subject><subject>Paleontology</subject><subject>Philosophers</subject><subject>Philosophy</subject><subject>Philosophy of Biology</subject><subject>Retirement benefits</subject><subject>Scientific method</subject><subject>Scientists</subject><subject>Training</subject><subject>Workers</subject><issn>0169-3867</issn><issn>1572-8404</issn><fulltext>true</fulltext><rsrctype>article</rsrctype><creationdate>2019</creationdate><recordtype>article</recordtype><sourceid>AFKRA</sourceid><sourceid>AZQEC</sourceid><sourceid>BENPR</sourceid><sourceid>CCPQU</sourceid><sourceid>DWQXO</sourceid><sourceid>GNUQQ</sourceid><recordid>eNp1kctKAzEUhoMoWKsP4K4gCC6mnmQylyxL8VIoCF7WIZOcaad0JjXJiL69KRVqQckicPi-XP6fkEsKYwpQ3HoKWSoSoCIRecETdkQGNCtYUnLgx2QANBdJWubFKTnzfgUAOed0QMZPH-i0bZtuMQpLHPWdQWcwoIsjFRrbjWw98hvUTYudPycntVp7vPjZh-Tt_u51-pjMnx5m08k80VzQkHCgvCoBNRqdG8OxylStS4BK0FwrUzCam4zXOkvji1MsBYqSVWlBRVVXRqdDcrU7d-Pse48-yJXtXRevlIwBKyjLGeyphVqjbLraBqd023gtJ1lJGePxj5Ea_0HFZbBttO2wbuL8QLg5ECIT8DMsVO-9nL08H7LXv9glqnVYervut8n5Q5DuQO2s9w5ruXFNq9yXpCC3FcpdhTIGIrcVShYdtnN8ZLsFun0K_0vfQ-yatA</recordid><startdate>20190403</startdate><enddate>20190403</enddate><creator>Wylie, Caitlin Donahue</creator><general>Springer Netherlands</general><general>Springer</general><general>Springer Nature B.V</general><scope>AAYXX</scope><scope>CITATION</scope><scope>ISR</scope><scope>8FE</scope><scope>8FH</scope><scope>AABKS</scope><scope>ABSDQ</scope><scope>AFKRA</scope><scope>AZQEC</scope><scope>BBNVY</scope><scope>BENPR</scope><scope>BHPHI</scope><scope>CCPQU</scope><scope>DWQXO</scope><scope>GNUQQ</scope><scope>HCIFZ</scope><scope>LK8</scope><scope>M7P</scope><scope>PQEST</scope><scope>PQQKQ</scope><scope>PQUKI</scope><scope>PRINS</scope><orcidid>https://orcid.org/0000-0002-0214-7837</orcidid></search><sort><creationdate>20190403</creationdate><title>Overcoming the underdetermination of specimens</title><author>Wylie, Caitlin Donahue</author></sort><facets><frbrtype>5</frbrtype><frbrgroupid>cdi_FETCH-LOGICAL-c491t-4014b80ecedc6dd4eb5afc800b916cad7216d54fc530193e89e982b3719bfbdc3</frbrgroupid><rsrctype>articles</rsrctype><prefilter>articles</prefilter><language>eng</language><creationdate>2019</creationdate><topic>Archaeology</topic><topic>Data processing</topic><topic>Division of labor</topic><topic>Education</topic><topic>Evolutionary Biology</topic><topic>Fossils</topic><topic>Material culture</topic><topic>Paleobiology and Philosophy</topic><topic>Paleontology</topic><topic>Philosophers</topic><topic>Philosophy</topic><topic>Philosophy of Biology</topic><topic>Retirement benefits</topic><topic>Scientific method</topic><topic>Scientists</topic><topic>Training</topic><topic>Workers</topic><toplevel>peer_reviewed</toplevel><toplevel>online_resources</toplevel><creatorcontrib>Wylie, Caitlin Donahue</creatorcontrib><collection>CrossRef</collection><collection>Gale In Context: Science</collection><collection>ProQuest SciTech Collection</collection><collection>ProQuest Natural Science Collection</collection><collection>Philosophy Collection</collection><collection>Philosophy Database</collection><collection>ProQuest Central UK/Ireland</collection><collection>ProQuest Central Essentials</collection><collection>Biological Science Collection</collection><collection>ProQuest Central</collection><collection>Natural Science Collection</collection><collection>ProQuest One Community College</collection><collection>ProQuest Central Korea</collection><collection>ProQuest Central Student</collection><collection>SciTech Premium Collection</collection><collection>ProQuest Biological Science Collection</collection><collection>Biological Science Database</collection><collection>ProQuest One Academic Eastern Edition (DO NOT USE)</collection><collection>ProQuest One Academic</collection><collection>ProQuest One Academic UKI Edition</collection><collection>ProQuest Central China</collection><jtitle>Biology &amp; philosophy</jtitle></facets><delivery><delcategory>Remote Search Resource</delcategory><fulltext>fulltext</fulltext></delivery><addata><au>Wylie, Caitlin Donahue</au><format>journal</format><genre>article</genre><ristype>JOUR</ristype><atitle>Overcoming the underdetermination of specimens</atitle><jtitle>Biology &amp; philosophy</jtitle><stitle>Biol Philos</stitle><date>2019-04-03</date><risdate>2019</risdate><volume>34</volume><issue>2</issue><spage>1</spage><epage>18</epage><pages>1-18</pages><artnum>24</artnum><issn>0169-3867</issn><eissn>1572-8404</eissn><abstract>Philosophers of science are well aware that theories are underdetermined by data. But what about the data? Scientific data are selected and processed representations or pieces of nature. What is useless context and what is valuable specimen, as well as how specimens are processed for study, are not obvious or predetermined givens. Instead, they are decisions made by scientists and other research workers, such as technicians, that produce different outcomes for the data. Vertebrate fossils provide a revealing case of this data-processing, because they are embedded in rock that often matches the fossils’ color and texture, requiring an expert eye to judge where the fossil/context interface is. Fossil preparators then permanently define this interface by chiseling away the material they identify as rock. As a result, fossil specimens can emerge in multiple possible forms depending on the preparator’s judgment, skill, and chosen tools. A prepared fossil then is not yet data but potential data, following Leonelli’s (Philos Sci 82:810–821, 2015 . https://doi.org/10.1086/684083 ) relational framework in which data are defined as evidence that scientists have used to support a proposed theory. This paper draws on ethnographic evidence to assess how scientists overcome this underdetermination of specimens, as potential data, in addition to the underdetermination of theories and of data, to successfully construct specimen-based knowledge. Among other strategies, paleontology maintains a division of labor between data-makers and theory-makers. This distinction serves to justify the omission of preparators’ nonstandard, individualized techniques from scientific publications. This separation has benefits for both scientists and technicians; however, it restricts knowledge production by preventing scientists from understanding how the pieces of nature they study were processed into researchable specimens.</abstract><cop>Dordrecht</cop><pub>Springer Netherlands</pub><doi>10.1007/s10539-019-9674-2</doi><tpages>18</tpages><orcidid>https://orcid.org/0000-0002-0214-7837</orcidid><oa>free_for_read</oa></addata></record>
fulltext fulltext
identifier ISSN: 0169-3867
ispartof Biology & philosophy, 2019-04, Vol.34 (2), p.1-18, Article 24
issn 0169-3867
1572-8404
language eng
recordid cdi_proquest_journals_2202712620
source SpringerNature Journals
subjects Archaeology
Data processing
Division of labor
Education
Evolutionary Biology
Fossils
Material culture
Paleobiology and Philosophy
Paleontology
Philosophers
Philosophy
Philosophy of Biology
Retirement benefits
Scientific method
Scientists
Training
Workers
title Overcoming the underdetermination of specimens
url https://sfx.bib-bvb.de/sfx_tum?ctx_ver=Z39.88-2004&ctx_enc=info:ofi/enc:UTF-8&ctx_tim=2024-12-02T19%3A34%3A45IST&url_ver=Z39.88-2004&url_ctx_fmt=infofi/fmt:kev:mtx:ctx&rfr_id=info:sid/primo.exlibrisgroup.com:primo3-Article-gale_proqu&rft_val_fmt=info:ofi/fmt:kev:mtx:journal&rft.genre=article&rft.atitle=Overcoming%20the%20underdetermination%20of%20specimens&rft.jtitle=Biology%20&%20philosophy&rft.au=Wylie,%20Caitlin%20Donahue&rft.date=2019-04-03&rft.volume=34&rft.issue=2&rft.spage=1&rft.epage=18&rft.pages=1-18&rft.artnum=24&rft.issn=0169-3867&rft.eissn=1572-8404&rft_id=info:doi/10.1007/s10539-019-9674-2&rft_dat=%3Cgale_proqu%3EA581224441%3C/gale_proqu%3E%3Curl%3E%3C/url%3E&disable_directlink=true&sfx.directlink=off&sfx.report_link=0&rft_id=info:oai/&rft_pqid=2202712620&rft_id=info:pmid/&rft_galeid=A581224441&rfr_iscdi=true