Human Rights and the Political Paradox

Rather it is predicated on a common understanding of what makes human life intolerable (Ignatieff56).6 This consensus is negative in that it requires only a limited form of reciprocity according to which we consider what it is in our mutual interest to avoid in political life (Shklar 10). Since it i...

Ausführliche Beschreibung

Gespeichert in:
Bibliographische Detailangaben
Veröffentlicht in:Australian humanities review 2013-11 (55), p.N_A
1. Verfasser: Schaap, Andrew
Format: Artikel
Sprache:eng
Schlagworte:
Online-Zugang:Volltext
Tags: Tag hinzufügen
Keine Tags, Fügen Sie den ersten Tag hinzu!
container_end_page
container_issue 55
container_start_page N_A
container_title Australian humanities review
container_volume
creator Schaap, Andrew
description Rather it is predicated on a common understanding of what makes human life intolerable (Ignatieff56).6 This consensus is negative in that it requires only a limited form of reciprocity according to which we consider what it is in our mutual interest to avoid in political life (Shklar 10). Since it is not possible to 'conceive of any circumstances in which we might excuse [human rights violations such as torture] against ourselves or anyone we know, we have good reason to believe that such practices should be outlawed' (Ignatieff89).7 The cosmopolitan basis of human rights is thus premised on the universality of fear, which becomes politically relevant when its object is the cruelty inflicted by the state (Ignatieff80; Shklar 11).8 If what binds the community of human rights holders together is a shared aversion to the abuse of state power, what makes a shared commitment to human rights possible is a 'pragmatic silence on ultimate questions' (Ignatieff78). In Lefort's view, Marx accepts liberal philosophy's image of civil society as composed of individuals and its reduction of human rights to individual rights (Democracy 30). Since Marx remains trapped by liberalism's atomistic representation of civil society, he fails to recognize the implicit communal character of human rights (Democracy 32).17 The 'private' freedoms declared to be the rights of man, Lefort argues, also inaugurate in practice a 'new mode of access to the public sphere' (Lefort, Political Forms 249). According to Lefort, Marx's heteronymous view of politics as a product of socio-economic conditions does not allow him to grasp 'the historical mutation in which power is assigned limits and right is fully recognized as existing outside power' (Political Forms 254). [...]it remains to be considered what role human rights might play in a politics of transformation (see Balibar, 'Three concepts'; Ingram 'Democracy') that acts precisely on the non-political conditions that continue to shape political life.
format Article
fullrecord <record><control><sourceid>proquest</sourceid><recordid>TN_cdi_proquest_journals_1467865942</recordid><sourceformat>XML</sourceformat><sourcesystem>PC</sourcesystem><sourcerecordid>3156049741</sourcerecordid><originalsourceid>FETCH-proquest_journals_14678659423</originalsourceid><addsrcrecordid>eNpjYuA0NDYy1bUwNrZgQWJzMHAVF2cZGBiZGhiacjKoeZTmJuYpBGWmZ5QUKyTmpSiUZKQqBOTnZJZkJifmKAQkFiWm5FfwMLCmJeYUp_JCaW4GZTfXEGcP3YKi_MLS1OKS-Kz80qI8oFS8oYmZuYWZqaWJkTFxqgDVRTBA</addsrcrecordid><sourcetype>Aggregation Database</sourcetype><iscdi>true</iscdi><recordtype>article</recordtype><pqid>1467865942</pqid></control><display><type>article</type><title>Human Rights and the Political Paradox</title><source>Elektronische Zeitschriftenbibliothek - Frei zugängliche E-Journals</source><creator>Schaap, Andrew</creator><creatorcontrib>Schaap, Andrew</creatorcontrib><description>Rather it is predicated on a common understanding of what makes human life intolerable (Ignatieff56).6 This consensus is negative in that it requires only a limited form of reciprocity according to which we consider what it is in our mutual interest to avoid in political life (Shklar 10). Since it is not possible to 'conceive of any circumstances in which we might excuse [human rights violations such as torture] against ourselves or anyone we know, we have good reason to believe that such practices should be outlawed' (Ignatieff89).7 The cosmopolitan basis of human rights is thus premised on the universality of fear, which becomes politically relevant when its object is the cruelty inflicted by the state (Ignatieff80; Shklar 11).8 If what binds the community of human rights holders together is a shared aversion to the abuse of state power, what makes a shared commitment to human rights possible is a 'pragmatic silence on ultimate questions' (Ignatieff78). In Lefort's view, Marx accepts liberal philosophy's image of civil society as composed of individuals and its reduction of human rights to individual rights (Democracy 30). Since Marx remains trapped by liberalism's atomistic representation of civil society, he fails to recognize the implicit communal character of human rights (Democracy 32).17 The 'private' freedoms declared to be the rights of man, Lefort argues, also inaugurate in practice a 'new mode of access to the public sphere' (Lefort, Political Forms 249). According to Lefort, Marx's heteronymous view of politics as a product of socio-economic conditions does not allow him to grasp 'the historical mutation in which power is assigned limits and right is fully recognized as existing outside power' (Political Forms 254). [...]it remains to be considered what role human rights might play in a politics of transformation (see Balibar, 'Three concepts'; Ingram 'Democracy') that acts precisely on the non-political conditions that continue to shape political life.</description><identifier>ISSN: 1325-8338</identifier><identifier>EISSN: 1325-8338</identifier><language>eng</language><publisher>Bundoora: Association for the Study of Australian Literature (ASAL)</publisher><subject>Arendt, Hannah ; Associations ; Citizens ; Citizenship ; Good &amp; evil ; Human rights ; Marxism ; Military exercises ; Philosophy ; Politics ; Pragmatism ; Rationality ; Ricoeur, Paul ; Traditions ; Violence ; Weber, Max (1864-1920)</subject><ispartof>Australian humanities review, 2013-11 (55), p.N_A</ispartof><rights>Copyright Association for the Study of Australian Literature (ASAL) Nov 2013</rights><lds50>peer_reviewed</lds50><oa>free_for_read</oa><woscitedreferencessubscribed>false</woscitedreferencessubscribed></display><links><openurl>$$Topenurl_article</openurl><openurlfulltext>$$Topenurlfull_article</openurlfulltext><thumbnail>$$Tsyndetics_thumb_exl</thumbnail><link.rule.ids>314,777,781</link.rule.ids></links><search><creatorcontrib>Schaap, Andrew</creatorcontrib><title>Human Rights and the Political Paradox</title><title>Australian humanities review</title><description>Rather it is predicated on a common understanding of what makes human life intolerable (Ignatieff56).6 This consensus is negative in that it requires only a limited form of reciprocity according to which we consider what it is in our mutual interest to avoid in political life (Shklar 10). Since it is not possible to 'conceive of any circumstances in which we might excuse [human rights violations such as torture] against ourselves or anyone we know, we have good reason to believe that such practices should be outlawed' (Ignatieff89).7 The cosmopolitan basis of human rights is thus premised on the universality of fear, which becomes politically relevant when its object is the cruelty inflicted by the state (Ignatieff80; Shklar 11).8 If what binds the community of human rights holders together is a shared aversion to the abuse of state power, what makes a shared commitment to human rights possible is a 'pragmatic silence on ultimate questions' (Ignatieff78). In Lefort's view, Marx accepts liberal philosophy's image of civil society as composed of individuals and its reduction of human rights to individual rights (Democracy 30). Since Marx remains trapped by liberalism's atomistic representation of civil society, he fails to recognize the implicit communal character of human rights (Democracy 32).17 The 'private' freedoms declared to be the rights of man, Lefort argues, also inaugurate in practice a 'new mode of access to the public sphere' (Lefort, Political Forms 249). According to Lefort, Marx's heteronymous view of politics as a product of socio-economic conditions does not allow him to grasp 'the historical mutation in which power is assigned limits and right is fully recognized as existing outside power' (Political Forms 254). [...]it remains to be considered what role human rights might play in a politics of transformation (see Balibar, 'Three concepts'; Ingram 'Democracy') that acts precisely on the non-political conditions that continue to shape political life.</description><subject>Arendt, Hannah</subject><subject>Associations</subject><subject>Citizens</subject><subject>Citizenship</subject><subject>Good &amp; evil</subject><subject>Human rights</subject><subject>Marxism</subject><subject>Military exercises</subject><subject>Philosophy</subject><subject>Politics</subject><subject>Pragmatism</subject><subject>Rationality</subject><subject>Ricoeur, Paul</subject><subject>Traditions</subject><subject>Violence</subject><subject>Weber, Max (1864-1920)</subject><issn>1325-8338</issn><issn>1325-8338</issn><fulltext>true</fulltext><rsrctype>article</rsrctype><creationdate>2013</creationdate><recordtype>article</recordtype><sourceid>ABUWG</sourceid><sourceid>AFKRA</sourceid><sourceid>AIMQZ</sourceid><sourceid>AZQEC</sourceid><sourceid>BENPR</sourceid><sourceid>CCPQU</sourceid><sourceid>DWQXO</sourceid><sourceid>PAF</sourceid><sourceid>PQLNA</sourceid><sourceid>PROLI</sourceid><recordid>eNpjYuA0NDYy1bUwNrZgQWJzMHAVF2cZGBiZGhiacjKoeZTmJuYpBGWmZ5QUKyTmpSiUZKQqBOTnZJZkJifmKAQkFiWm5FfwMLCmJeYUp_JCaW4GZTfXEGcP3YKi_MLS1OKS-Kz80qI8oFS8oYmZuYWZqaWJkTFxqgDVRTBA</recordid><startdate>20131101</startdate><enddate>20131101</enddate><creator>Schaap, Andrew</creator><general>Association for the Study of Australian Literature (ASAL)</general><scope>ABUWG</scope><scope>AFKRA</scope><scope>AIMQZ</scope><scope>AYAGU</scope><scope>AZQEC</scope><scope>BENPR</scope><scope>CCPQU</scope><scope>CLO</scope><scope>DWQXO</scope><scope>LIQON</scope><scope>PAF</scope><scope>PIMPY</scope><scope>PPXUT</scope><scope>PQEST</scope><scope>PQLNA</scope><scope>PQQKQ</scope><scope>PQUKI</scope><scope>PRINS</scope><scope>PROLI</scope></search><sort><creationdate>20131101</creationdate><title>Human Rights and the Political Paradox</title><author>Schaap, Andrew</author></sort><facets><frbrtype>5</frbrtype><frbrgroupid>cdi_FETCH-proquest_journals_14678659423</frbrgroupid><rsrctype>articles</rsrctype><prefilter>articles</prefilter><language>eng</language><creationdate>2013</creationdate><topic>Arendt, Hannah</topic><topic>Associations</topic><topic>Citizens</topic><topic>Citizenship</topic><topic>Good &amp; evil</topic><topic>Human rights</topic><topic>Marxism</topic><topic>Military exercises</topic><topic>Philosophy</topic><topic>Politics</topic><topic>Pragmatism</topic><topic>Rationality</topic><topic>Ricoeur, Paul</topic><topic>Traditions</topic><topic>Violence</topic><topic>Weber, Max (1864-1920)</topic><toplevel>peer_reviewed</toplevel><toplevel>online_resources</toplevel><creatorcontrib>Schaap, Andrew</creatorcontrib><collection>ProQuest Central (Alumni Edition)</collection><collection>ProQuest Central UK/Ireland</collection><collection>ProQuest One Literature</collection><collection>Australia &amp; New Zealand Database</collection><collection>ProQuest Central Essentials</collection><collection>ProQuest Central</collection><collection>ProQuest One Community College</collection><collection>Literature Online Core (LION Core) (legacy)</collection><collection>ProQuest Central Korea</collection><collection>ProQuest One Literature - U.S. Customers Only</collection><collection>ProQuest Learning: Literature</collection><collection>Publicly Available Content Database</collection><collection>Literature Online Premium (LION Premium) (legacy)</collection><collection>ProQuest One Academic Eastern Edition (DO NOT USE)</collection><collection>Literature Online (LION) - US Customers Only</collection><collection>ProQuest One Academic</collection><collection>ProQuest One Academic UKI Edition</collection><collection>ProQuest Central China</collection><collection>Literature Online (LION)</collection><jtitle>Australian humanities review</jtitle></facets><delivery><delcategory>Remote Search Resource</delcategory><fulltext>fulltext</fulltext></delivery><addata><au>Schaap, Andrew</au><format>journal</format><genre>article</genre><ristype>JOUR</ristype><atitle>Human Rights and the Political Paradox</atitle><jtitle>Australian humanities review</jtitle><date>2013-11-01</date><risdate>2013</risdate><issue>55</issue><spage>N_A</spage><pages>N_A-</pages><issn>1325-8338</issn><eissn>1325-8338</eissn><abstract>Rather it is predicated on a common understanding of what makes human life intolerable (Ignatieff56).6 This consensus is negative in that it requires only a limited form of reciprocity according to which we consider what it is in our mutual interest to avoid in political life (Shklar 10). Since it is not possible to 'conceive of any circumstances in which we might excuse [human rights violations such as torture] against ourselves or anyone we know, we have good reason to believe that such practices should be outlawed' (Ignatieff89).7 The cosmopolitan basis of human rights is thus premised on the universality of fear, which becomes politically relevant when its object is the cruelty inflicted by the state (Ignatieff80; Shklar 11).8 If what binds the community of human rights holders together is a shared aversion to the abuse of state power, what makes a shared commitment to human rights possible is a 'pragmatic silence on ultimate questions' (Ignatieff78). In Lefort's view, Marx accepts liberal philosophy's image of civil society as composed of individuals and its reduction of human rights to individual rights (Democracy 30). Since Marx remains trapped by liberalism's atomistic representation of civil society, he fails to recognize the implicit communal character of human rights (Democracy 32).17 The 'private' freedoms declared to be the rights of man, Lefort argues, also inaugurate in practice a 'new mode of access to the public sphere' (Lefort, Political Forms 249). According to Lefort, Marx's heteronymous view of politics as a product of socio-economic conditions does not allow him to grasp 'the historical mutation in which power is assigned limits and right is fully recognized as existing outside power' (Political Forms 254). [...]it remains to be considered what role human rights might play in a politics of transformation (see Balibar, 'Three concepts'; Ingram 'Democracy') that acts precisely on the non-political conditions that continue to shape political life.</abstract><cop>Bundoora</cop><pub>Association for the Study of Australian Literature (ASAL)</pub><oa>free_for_read</oa></addata></record>
fulltext fulltext
identifier ISSN: 1325-8338
ispartof Australian humanities review, 2013-11 (55), p.N_A
issn 1325-8338
1325-8338
language eng
recordid cdi_proquest_journals_1467865942
source Elektronische Zeitschriftenbibliothek - Frei zugängliche E-Journals
subjects Arendt, Hannah
Associations
Citizens
Citizenship
Good & evil
Human rights
Marxism
Military exercises
Philosophy
Politics
Pragmatism
Rationality
Ricoeur, Paul
Traditions
Violence
Weber, Max (1864-1920)
title Human Rights and the Political Paradox
url https://sfx.bib-bvb.de/sfx_tum?ctx_ver=Z39.88-2004&ctx_enc=info:ofi/enc:UTF-8&ctx_tim=2025-01-21T02%3A36%3A59IST&url_ver=Z39.88-2004&url_ctx_fmt=infofi/fmt:kev:mtx:ctx&rfr_id=info:sid/primo.exlibrisgroup.com:primo3-Article-proquest&rft_val_fmt=info:ofi/fmt:kev:mtx:journal&rft.genre=article&rft.atitle=Human%20Rights%20and%20the%20Political%20Paradox&rft.jtitle=Australian%20humanities%20review&rft.au=Schaap,%20Andrew&rft.date=2013-11-01&rft.issue=55&rft.spage=N_A&rft.pages=N_A-&rft.issn=1325-8338&rft.eissn=1325-8338&rft_id=info:doi/&rft_dat=%3Cproquest%3E3156049741%3C/proquest%3E%3Curl%3E%3C/url%3E&disable_directlink=true&sfx.directlink=off&sfx.report_link=0&rft_id=info:oai/&rft_pqid=1467865942&rft_id=info:pmid/&rfr_iscdi=true