Comparative vs. Transcendental Approaches to Justice: A Misleading Dichotomy in Sen's The Idea of Justice

This paper examines the distinction drawn by Amartya Sen between transcendental and comparative theories of justice, and its application to Rawls' doctrine. It then puts forward three arguments. First, it is argued that Sen offers a limited portrayal of Rawls' doctrine. This is the result...

Ausführliche Beschreibung

Gespeichert in:
Bibliographische Detailangaben
Veröffentlicht in:Ratio juris 2012-12, Vol.25 (4), p.555-577
1. Verfasser: Biondo, Francesco
Format: Artikel
Sprache:eng
Schlagworte:
Online-Zugang:Volltext
Tags: Tag hinzufügen
Keine Tags, Fügen Sie den ersten Tag hinzu!
container_end_page 577
container_issue 4
container_start_page 555
container_title Ratio juris
container_volume 25
creator Biondo, Francesco
description This paper examines the distinction drawn by Amartya Sen between transcendental and comparative theories of justice, and its application to Rawls' doctrine. It then puts forward three arguments. First, it is argued that Sen offers a limited portrayal of Rawls' doctrine. This is the result of a rhetorical strategy that depicts Rawlsian doctrine as more “transcendental” than it really is. Although Sen deploys numerous quotations in support of his interpretation, it is possible to offer a less transcendental interpretation of Rawls. Second, the dichotomy between transcendental and comparative approaches to questions of justice is partly misleading, insofar as any plausible moral doctrine has both transcendental and comparative elements. Transcendental elements are necessary to avoid the confusion between the general acceptance of a norm, value or principle and its justification. A comparative view highlights the conditions of application of the doctrine to the real world, taking into account the possibility of moral dilemmas, evaluative disagreements and limited resources, while proposing possible provisos and caveats to the risk of the doctrine being self‐defeating. Third, although the transcendental approach is useful, it is argued that in elaborating this dichotomy Sen overlooks the merits of the third way between comparative and transcendental doctrines, what he calls “conglomerate theory,” and also the possibility that his doctrine (the capability approach) might be considered as an example of such a theory. The paper concludes with the argument that conglomerate theory does not aim to produce complete moral orderings, but rather a comparative approach with transcendental elements, as a form of weak transcendentalism.
doi_str_mv 10.1111/j.1467-9337.2012.00527.x
format Article
fullrecord <record><control><sourceid>proquest_wiley</sourceid><recordid>TN_cdi_proquest_journals_1170954191</recordid><sourceformat>XML</sourceformat><sourcesystem>PC</sourcesystem><sourcerecordid>2819187301</sourcerecordid><originalsourceid>FETCH-LOGICAL-i2487-5a49f22ac1427e042888296839426845ce64d5b85710ed898bb8b4c6301fb4d33</originalsourceid><addsrcrecordid>eNo9kFFPgzAUhRujiXP6H5r44BPYlkKLiQ84dW5OjY7FxJemQHHFDZCyuf17i1Pvy73JPefekw8AiJGLbZ0XLqYBc0LPYy5BmLgI-YS5mz3Q-1_sgx4KfeLgELNDcGRMgazKC2kP6EG1rGUjW71WcG1cGDeyNKkqM1W2cgGjum4qmc6VgW0FxyvT6lRdwAg-aLNQMtPlO7zW6bxqq-UW6hJOVXlmYDxXcJQpCav8z3QMDnK5MOrkt_fB7PYmHtw5k6fhaBBNHE0oZ44vaZgTIlNMCVOIEs45CQNu05KAUz9VAc38hPsMI5XxkCcJT2gaeAjnCc08rw9Od3dt8M-VMq0oqlVT2pcCY2Y5UIvBqi53qi-9UFtRN3opm63ASHRURSE6eKKDJzqq4oeq2IiXaDyzk_U7O782rdr8-2XzIQLmMV-8Pg7FFbmnb8_TWATeN-oaewQ</addsrcrecordid><sourcetype>Aggregation Database</sourcetype><iscdi>true</iscdi><recordtype>article</recordtype><pqid>1170954191</pqid></control><display><type>article</type><title>Comparative vs. Transcendental Approaches to Justice: A Misleading Dichotomy in Sen's The Idea of Justice</title><source>Wiley Online Library All Journals</source><source>HeinOnline Law Journal Library</source><creator>Biondo, Francesco</creator><creatorcontrib>Biondo, Francesco</creatorcontrib><description>This paper examines the distinction drawn by Amartya Sen between transcendental and comparative theories of justice, and its application to Rawls' doctrine. It then puts forward three arguments. First, it is argued that Sen offers a limited portrayal of Rawls' doctrine. This is the result of a rhetorical strategy that depicts Rawlsian doctrine as more “transcendental” than it really is. Although Sen deploys numerous quotations in support of his interpretation, it is possible to offer a less transcendental interpretation of Rawls. Second, the dichotomy between transcendental and comparative approaches to questions of justice is partly misleading, insofar as any plausible moral doctrine has both transcendental and comparative elements. Transcendental elements are necessary to avoid the confusion between the general acceptance of a norm, value or principle and its justification. A comparative view highlights the conditions of application of the doctrine to the real world, taking into account the possibility of moral dilemmas, evaluative disagreements and limited resources, while proposing possible provisos and caveats to the risk of the doctrine being self‐defeating. Third, although the transcendental approach is useful, it is argued that in elaborating this dichotomy Sen overlooks the merits of the third way between comparative and transcendental doctrines, what he calls “conglomerate theory,” and also the possibility that his doctrine (the capability approach) might be considered as an example of such a theory. The paper concludes with the argument that conglomerate theory does not aim to produce complete moral orderings, but rather a comparative approach with transcendental elements, as a form of weak transcendentalism.</description><identifier>ISSN: 0952-1917</identifier><identifier>EISSN: 1467-9337</identifier><identifier>DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9337.2012.00527.x</identifier><language>eng</language><publisher>Oxford: Blackwell Publishing Ltd</publisher><subject>Justice ; Law ; Morality ; Transcendentalism</subject><ispartof>Ratio juris, 2012-12, Vol.25 (4), p.555-577</ispartof><rights>2012 The Author. Ratio Juris © 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd</rights><rights>Journal compilation © 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd</rights><woscitedreferencessubscribed>false</woscitedreferencessubscribed></display><links><openurl>$$Topenurl_article</openurl><openurlfulltext>$$Topenurlfull_article</openurlfulltext><thumbnail>$$Tsyndetics_thumb_exl</thumbnail><linktopdf>$$Uhttps://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/pdf/10.1111%2Fj.1467-9337.2012.00527.x$$EPDF$$P50$$Gwiley$$H</linktopdf><linktohtml>$$Uhttps://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/full/10.1111%2Fj.1467-9337.2012.00527.x$$EHTML$$P50$$Gwiley$$H</linktohtml><link.rule.ids>314,776,780,1411,27901,27902,45550,45551</link.rule.ids></links><search><creatorcontrib>Biondo, Francesco</creatorcontrib><title>Comparative vs. Transcendental Approaches to Justice: A Misleading Dichotomy in Sen's The Idea of Justice</title><title>Ratio juris</title><addtitle>Ratio Juris</addtitle><description>This paper examines the distinction drawn by Amartya Sen between transcendental and comparative theories of justice, and its application to Rawls' doctrine. It then puts forward three arguments. First, it is argued that Sen offers a limited portrayal of Rawls' doctrine. This is the result of a rhetorical strategy that depicts Rawlsian doctrine as more “transcendental” than it really is. Although Sen deploys numerous quotations in support of his interpretation, it is possible to offer a less transcendental interpretation of Rawls. Second, the dichotomy between transcendental and comparative approaches to questions of justice is partly misleading, insofar as any plausible moral doctrine has both transcendental and comparative elements. Transcendental elements are necessary to avoid the confusion between the general acceptance of a norm, value or principle and its justification. A comparative view highlights the conditions of application of the doctrine to the real world, taking into account the possibility of moral dilemmas, evaluative disagreements and limited resources, while proposing possible provisos and caveats to the risk of the doctrine being self‐defeating. Third, although the transcendental approach is useful, it is argued that in elaborating this dichotomy Sen overlooks the merits of the third way between comparative and transcendental doctrines, what he calls “conglomerate theory,” and also the possibility that his doctrine (the capability approach) might be considered as an example of such a theory. The paper concludes with the argument that conglomerate theory does not aim to produce complete moral orderings, but rather a comparative approach with transcendental elements, as a form of weak transcendentalism.</description><subject>Justice</subject><subject>Law</subject><subject>Morality</subject><subject>Transcendentalism</subject><issn>0952-1917</issn><issn>1467-9337</issn><fulltext>true</fulltext><rsrctype>article</rsrctype><creationdate>2012</creationdate><recordtype>article</recordtype><recordid>eNo9kFFPgzAUhRujiXP6H5r44BPYlkKLiQ84dW5OjY7FxJemQHHFDZCyuf17i1Pvy73JPefekw8AiJGLbZ0XLqYBc0LPYy5BmLgI-YS5mz3Q-1_sgx4KfeLgELNDcGRMgazKC2kP6EG1rGUjW71WcG1cGDeyNKkqM1W2cgGjum4qmc6VgW0FxyvT6lRdwAg-aLNQMtPlO7zW6bxqq-UW6hJOVXlmYDxXcJQpCav8z3QMDnK5MOrkt_fB7PYmHtw5k6fhaBBNHE0oZ44vaZgTIlNMCVOIEs45CQNu05KAUz9VAc38hPsMI5XxkCcJT2gaeAjnCc08rw9Od3dt8M-VMq0oqlVT2pcCY2Y5UIvBqi53qi-9UFtRN3opm63ASHRURSE6eKKDJzqq4oeq2IiXaDyzk_U7O782rdr8-2XzIQLmMV-8Pg7FFbmnb8_TWATeN-oaewQ</recordid><startdate>201212</startdate><enddate>201212</enddate><creator>Biondo, Francesco</creator><general>Blackwell Publishing Ltd</general><general>Wiley Subscription Services, Inc</general><scope>BSCLL</scope></search><sort><creationdate>201212</creationdate><title>Comparative vs. Transcendental Approaches to Justice: A Misleading Dichotomy in Sen's The Idea of Justice</title><author>Biondo, Francesco</author></sort><facets><frbrtype>5</frbrtype><frbrgroupid>cdi_FETCH-LOGICAL-i2487-5a49f22ac1427e042888296839426845ce64d5b85710ed898bb8b4c6301fb4d33</frbrgroupid><rsrctype>articles</rsrctype><prefilter>articles</prefilter><language>eng</language><creationdate>2012</creationdate><topic>Justice</topic><topic>Law</topic><topic>Morality</topic><topic>Transcendentalism</topic><toplevel>online_resources</toplevel><creatorcontrib>Biondo, Francesco</creatorcontrib><collection>Istex</collection><jtitle>Ratio juris</jtitle></facets><delivery><delcategory>Remote Search Resource</delcategory><fulltext>fulltext</fulltext></delivery><addata><au>Biondo, Francesco</au><format>journal</format><genre>article</genre><ristype>JOUR</ristype><atitle>Comparative vs. Transcendental Approaches to Justice: A Misleading Dichotomy in Sen's The Idea of Justice</atitle><jtitle>Ratio juris</jtitle><addtitle>Ratio Juris</addtitle><date>2012-12</date><risdate>2012</risdate><volume>25</volume><issue>4</issue><spage>555</spage><epage>577</epage><pages>555-577</pages><issn>0952-1917</issn><eissn>1467-9337</eissn><abstract>This paper examines the distinction drawn by Amartya Sen between transcendental and comparative theories of justice, and its application to Rawls' doctrine. It then puts forward three arguments. First, it is argued that Sen offers a limited portrayal of Rawls' doctrine. This is the result of a rhetorical strategy that depicts Rawlsian doctrine as more “transcendental” than it really is. Although Sen deploys numerous quotations in support of his interpretation, it is possible to offer a less transcendental interpretation of Rawls. Second, the dichotomy between transcendental and comparative approaches to questions of justice is partly misleading, insofar as any plausible moral doctrine has both transcendental and comparative elements. Transcendental elements are necessary to avoid the confusion between the general acceptance of a norm, value or principle and its justification. A comparative view highlights the conditions of application of the doctrine to the real world, taking into account the possibility of moral dilemmas, evaluative disagreements and limited resources, while proposing possible provisos and caveats to the risk of the doctrine being self‐defeating. Third, although the transcendental approach is useful, it is argued that in elaborating this dichotomy Sen overlooks the merits of the third way between comparative and transcendental doctrines, what he calls “conglomerate theory,” and also the possibility that his doctrine (the capability approach) might be considered as an example of such a theory. The paper concludes with the argument that conglomerate theory does not aim to produce complete moral orderings, but rather a comparative approach with transcendental elements, as a form of weak transcendentalism.</abstract><cop>Oxford</cop><pub>Blackwell Publishing Ltd</pub><doi>10.1111/j.1467-9337.2012.00527.x</doi><tpages>23</tpages></addata></record>
fulltext fulltext
identifier ISSN: 0952-1917
ispartof Ratio juris, 2012-12, Vol.25 (4), p.555-577
issn 0952-1917
1467-9337
language eng
recordid cdi_proquest_journals_1170954191
source Wiley Online Library All Journals; HeinOnline Law Journal Library
subjects Justice
Law
Morality
Transcendentalism
title Comparative vs. Transcendental Approaches to Justice: A Misleading Dichotomy in Sen's The Idea of Justice
url https://sfx.bib-bvb.de/sfx_tum?ctx_ver=Z39.88-2004&ctx_enc=info:ofi/enc:UTF-8&ctx_tim=2025-02-19T02%3A29%3A54IST&url_ver=Z39.88-2004&url_ctx_fmt=infofi/fmt:kev:mtx:ctx&rfr_id=info:sid/primo.exlibrisgroup.com:primo3-Article-proquest_wiley&rft_val_fmt=info:ofi/fmt:kev:mtx:journal&rft.genre=article&rft.atitle=Comparative%20vs.%20Transcendental%20Approaches%20to%20Justice:%20A%20Misleading%20Dichotomy%20in%20Sen's%20The%20Idea%20of%20Justice&rft.jtitle=Ratio%20juris&rft.au=Biondo,%20Francesco&rft.date=2012-12&rft.volume=25&rft.issue=4&rft.spage=555&rft.epage=577&rft.pages=555-577&rft.issn=0952-1917&rft.eissn=1467-9337&rft_id=info:doi/10.1111/j.1467-9337.2012.00527.x&rft_dat=%3Cproquest_wiley%3E2819187301%3C/proquest_wiley%3E%3Curl%3E%3C/url%3E&disable_directlink=true&sfx.directlink=off&sfx.report_link=0&rft_id=info:oai/&rft_pqid=1170954191&rft_id=info:pmid/&rfr_iscdi=true