Transcendence, Truth, and Argumentation

According to Thomas Nagel we have a natural impulse to transcend our personal point of view. However, it appears to be difficult to give this notion of transcendence any real content while maintaining a connection with everyday speech and behaviour. In this essay I show that the description of what...

Ausführliche Beschreibung

Gespeichert in:
Bibliographische Detailangaben
Veröffentlicht in:Inquiry: an interdisciplinary journal of philosophy 1998-12, Vol.41 (4), p.411-434
1. Verfasser: Heysse, Tim
Format: Artikel
Sprache:eng
Online-Zugang:Volltext bestellen
Tags: Tag hinzufügen
Keine Tags, Fügen Sie den ersten Tag hinzu!
container_end_page 434
container_issue 4
container_start_page 411
container_title Inquiry: an interdisciplinary journal of philosophy
container_volume 41
creator Heysse, Tim
description According to Thomas Nagel we have a natural impulse to transcend our personal point of view. However, it appears to be difficult to give this notion of transcendence any real content while maintaining a connection with everyday speech and behaviour. In this essay I show that the description of what happens in a discussion when a speaker convinces a listener suggests an interesting interpretation of transcendence. The notion of `truth' linked to the listener who is being convinced introduces a normative dimension in argumentation. This inescapable normative stance of the listener saddles her with the obligation to answer all credible objections against all arguments she has accepted. The evaluation of the arguments is not reserved for the participants of a discussion. Nothing more is required. For instance, the notion of a universal consensus has no place in the analysis of argumentation. If there is a universal dimension in argumentation and discussion, it is because there is no way of telling where convincing objections may come from.
format Article
fullrecord <record><control><sourceid>kuleuven_FZOIL</sourceid><recordid>TN_cdi_kuleuven_dspace_123456789_214888</recordid><sourceformat>XML</sourceformat><sourcesystem>PC</sourcesystem><sourcerecordid>123456789_214888</sourcerecordid><originalsourceid>FETCH-kuleuven_dspace_123456789_2148883</originalsourceid><addsrcrecordid>eNpjYeA0MDAy0DU0N4ngYOAqLs4yAPINzcw4GdRDihLzipNT81JS85JTdRRCikpLMnQUEvNSFByL0ktzU_NKEksy8_N4GFjTEnOKU3mhNDeDuptriLOHbnZpTmppWWpefEpxQWJyaryhkbGJqZm5hWW8kaGJhYWFMSkqtYlTGV9SUWIMADP2Pbc</addsrcrecordid><sourcetype>Institutional Repository</sourcetype><iscdi>true</iscdi><recordtype>article</recordtype></control><display><type>article</type><title>Transcendence, Truth, and Argumentation</title><source>Lirias (KU Leuven Association)</source><creator>Heysse, Tim</creator><creatorcontrib>Heysse, Tim</creatorcontrib><description>According to Thomas Nagel we have a natural impulse to transcend our personal point of view. However, it appears to be difficult to give this notion of transcendence any real content while maintaining a connection with everyday speech and behaviour. In this essay I show that the description of what happens in a discussion when a speaker convinces a listener suggests an interesting interpretation of transcendence. The notion of `truth' linked to the listener who is being convinced introduces a normative dimension in argumentation. This inescapable normative stance of the listener saddles her with the obligation to answer all credible objections against all arguments she has accepted. The evaluation of the arguments is not reserved for the participants of a discussion. Nothing more is required. For instance, the notion of a universal consensus has no place in the analysis of argumentation. If there is a universal dimension in argumentation and discussion, it is because there is no way of telling where convincing objections may come from.</description><identifier>ISSN: 0020-174X</identifier><language>eng</language><publisher>Routledge</publisher><ispartof>Inquiry: an interdisciplinary journal of philosophy, 1998-12, Vol.41 (4), p.411-434</ispartof><lds50>peer_reviewed</lds50><oa>free_for_read</oa><woscitedreferencessubscribed>false</woscitedreferencessubscribed></display><links><openurl>$$Topenurl_article</openurl><openurlfulltext>$$Topenurlfull_article</openurlfulltext><thumbnail>$$Tsyndetics_thumb_exl</thumbnail><link.rule.ids>315,780,27860</link.rule.ids><linktorsrc>$$Uhttps://lirias.kuleuven.be/handle/123456789/214888$$EView_record_in_KU_Leuven_Association$$FView_record_in_$$GKU_Leuven_Association$$Hfree_for_read</linktorsrc></links><search><creatorcontrib>Heysse, Tim</creatorcontrib><title>Transcendence, Truth, and Argumentation</title><title>Inquiry: an interdisciplinary journal of philosophy</title><description>According to Thomas Nagel we have a natural impulse to transcend our personal point of view. However, it appears to be difficult to give this notion of transcendence any real content while maintaining a connection with everyday speech and behaviour. In this essay I show that the description of what happens in a discussion when a speaker convinces a listener suggests an interesting interpretation of transcendence. The notion of `truth' linked to the listener who is being convinced introduces a normative dimension in argumentation. This inescapable normative stance of the listener saddles her with the obligation to answer all credible objections against all arguments she has accepted. The evaluation of the arguments is not reserved for the participants of a discussion. Nothing more is required. For instance, the notion of a universal consensus has no place in the analysis of argumentation. If there is a universal dimension in argumentation and discussion, it is because there is no way of telling where convincing objections may come from.</description><issn>0020-174X</issn><fulltext>true</fulltext><rsrctype>article</rsrctype><creationdate>1998</creationdate><recordtype>article</recordtype><sourceid>FZOIL</sourceid><recordid>eNpjYeA0MDAy0DU0N4ngYOAqLs4yAPINzcw4GdRDihLzipNT81JS85JTdRRCikpLMnQUEvNSFByL0ktzU_NKEksy8_N4GFjTEnOKU3mhNDeDuptriLOHbnZpTmppWWpefEpxQWJyaryhkbGJqZm5hWW8kaGJhYWFMSkqtYlTGV9SUWIMADP2Pbc</recordid><startdate>199812</startdate><enddate>199812</enddate><creator>Heysse, Tim</creator><general>Routledge</general><scope>FZOIL</scope></search><sort><creationdate>199812</creationdate><title>Transcendence, Truth, and Argumentation</title><author>Heysse, Tim</author></sort><facets><frbrtype>5</frbrtype><frbrgroupid>cdi_FETCH-kuleuven_dspace_123456789_2148883</frbrgroupid><rsrctype>articles</rsrctype><prefilter>articles</prefilter><language>eng</language><creationdate>1998</creationdate><toplevel>peer_reviewed</toplevel><toplevel>online_resources</toplevel><creatorcontrib>Heysse, Tim</creatorcontrib><collection>Lirias (KU Leuven Association)</collection><jtitle>Inquiry: an interdisciplinary journal of philosophy</jtitle></facets><delivery><delcategory>Remote Search Resource</delcategory><fulltext>fulltext_linktorsrc</fulltext></delivery><addata><au>Heysse, Tim</au><format>journal</format><genre>article</genre><ristype>JOUR</ristype><atitle>Transcendence, Truth, and Argumentation</atitle><jtitle>Inquiry: an interdisciplinary journal of philosophy</jtitle><date>1998-12</date><risdate>1998</risdate><volume>41</volume><issue>4</issue><spage>411</spage><epage>434</epage><pages>411-434</pages><issn>0020-174X</issn><abstract>According to Thomas Nagel we have a natural impulse to transcend our personal point of view. However, it appears to be difficult to give this notion of transcendence any real content while maintaining a connection with everyday speech and behaviour. In this essay I show that the description of what happens in a discussion when a speaker convinces a listener suggests an interesting interpretation of transcendence. The notion of `truth' linked to the listener who is being convinced introduces a normative dimension in argumentation. This inescapable normative stance of the listener saddles her with the obligation to answer all credible objections against all arguments she has accepted. The evaluation of the arguments is not reserved for the participants of a discussion. Nothing more is required. For instance, the notion of a universal consensus has no place in the analysis of argumentation. If there is a universal dimension in argumentation and discussion, it is because there is no way of telling where convincing objections may come from.</abstract><pub>Routledge</pub><oa>free_for_read</oa></addata></record>
fulltext fulltext_linktorsrc
identifier ISSN: 0020-174X
ispartof Inquiry: an interdisciplinary journal of philosophy, 1998-12, Vol.41 (4), p.411-434
issn 0020-174X
language eng
recordid cdi_kuleuven_dspace_123456789_214888
source Lirias (KU Leuven Association)
title Transcendence, Truth, and Argumentation
url https://sfx.bib-bvb.de/sfx_tum?ctx_ver=Z39.88-2004&ctx_enc=info:ofi/enc:UTF-8&ctx_tim=2024-12-18T22%3A54%3A59IST&url_ver=Z39.88-2004&url_ctx_fmt=infofi/fmt:kev:mtx:ctx&rfr_id=info:sid/primo.exlibrisgroup.com:primo3-Article-kuleuven_FZOIL&rft_val_fmt=info:ofi/fmt:kev:mtx:journal&rft.genre=article&rft.atitle=Transcendence,%20Truth,%20and%20Argumentation&rft.jtitle=Inquiry:%20an%20interdisciplinary%20journal%20of%20philosophy&rft.au=Heysse,%20Tim&rft.date=1998-12&rft.volume=41&rft.issue=4&rft.spage=411&rft.epage=434&rft.pages=411-434&rft.issn=0020-174X&rft_id=info:doi/&rft_dat=%3Ckuleuven_FZOIL%3E123456789_214888%3C/kuleuven_FZOIL%3E%3Curl%3E%3C/url%3E&disable_directlink=true&sfx.directlink=off&sfx.report_link=0&rft_id=info:oai/&rft_id=info:pmid/&rfr_iscdi=true